Feminist Epistemology
and Philosophy of Science
First published Wed Aug 9, 2000; substantive revision Thu Aug 12, 2010
Feminist epistemology and philosophy of science studies the ways in
which gender does and ought to influence our conceptions of knowledge,
the knowing subject, and practices of inquiry and justification. It
identifies ways in which dominant conceptions and practices of
knowledge attribution, acquisition, and justification systematically
disadvantage women and other subordinated groups, and strives to reform
these conceptions and practices so that they serve the interests of
these groups. Various practitioners of feminist epistemology and
philosophy of science argue that dominant knowledge practices
disadvantage women by (1) excluding them from inquiry, (2) denying them
epistemic authority, (3) denigrating their “feminine” cognitive styles
and modes of knowledge, (4) producing theories of women that represent
them as inferior, deviant, or significant only in the ways they serve
male interests, (5) producing theories of social phenomena that render
women's activities and interests, or gendered power relations,
invisible, and (6) producing knowledge (science and technology) that is
not useful for people in subordinate positions, or that reinforces
gender and other social hierarchies. Feminist epistemologists trace
these failures to flawed conceptions of knowledge, knowers,
objectivity, and scientific methodology. They offer diverse accounts of
how to overcome these failures. They also aim to (1) explain why the
entry of women and feminist scholars into different academic
disciplines, especially in biology and the social sciences, has
generated new questions, theories, and methods, (2) show how gender has
played a causal role in these transformations, and (3) defend these
changes as cognitive, not just social, advances.
The central concept of feminist epistemology is that of a situated
knower, and hence of situated knowledge: knowledge that reflects the
particular perspectives of the subject. Feminist philosophers are
interested in how gender situates knowing subjects. They have
articulated three main approaches to this question: feminist standpoint
theory, feminist postmodernism, and feminist empiricism. Different
conceptions of how gender situates knowers also inform feminist
approaches to the central problems of the field: grounding feminist
criticisms of science and feminist science, defining the proper roles
of social and political values in inquiry, evaluating ideals of
objectivity and rationality, and reforming structures of epistemic
authority.
Feminist epistemology conceives of knowers as situated in particular
relations to what is known and to other knowers. What is known, and the
way that it is known, thereby reflects the situation or perspective of
the knower. Here we are concerned with claims to know, temporarily
bracketing the question of which claims are true or warranted.
Situated knowledge in general. Consider how people may understand the
same object in different ways that reflect the distinct relations in
which they stand to it.
Embodiment. People experience the world by using their bodies, which
have different constitutions and are differently located in space and
time. In virtue of their different physical locations, observers who
stand in front of an object have different information about it than
observers who have a distant but bird's eye view of it.
First-person vs. third-person knowledge. People have first-personal
access to some of their own bodily and mental states, yielding direct
knowledge of phenomenological facts about what it is like for them to
be in these states. Third parties may know these states only by
interpreting external symptoms, imaginative projection, or obtaining
their testimony. People also have knowledge de se about themselves,
expressed in the form “I am F here, now.” This is distinct in character
and inferential role from propositional knowledge having the same
content, which does not use indexicals.
Emotions, attitudes, interests, and values. People often represent
objects in relation to their emotions, attitudes and interests. A thief
represents a lock as a frustrating obstacle while its owner represents
the lock as a comforting source of security.
Personal knowledge of others. People have different knowledge of
others, in virtue of their different personal relationships to them.
Such knowledge is often tacit, incompletely articulated, and intuitive.
Like the knowledge it takes to get a joke, it is more an interpretive
skill in making sense of a person than a set of propositions. (The
German language usefully marks this as the distinction between
Erkenntnis and Wissenschaft.) Because people behave differently toward
others, and others interpret their behavior differently, depending on
their personal relationships, what others know of them depends on these
relationships. Know-how. People have different skills, which may also
be a source of different propositional knowledge. An expert dog handler
knows how to elicit more interesting behavior from an a dog than a
novice does. Such know-how expresses a more sophisticated understanding
of dogs on the part of the expert, and also generates new phenomena
about dogs for investigation.
Cognitive Styles. People have different styles of investigation and
representation. What looks like one phenomenon to a lumper may look
like three to a splitter. Background beliefs and worldviews. People
form different beliefs about an object, in virtue of different
background beliefs. In virtue of the different background beliefs
against which they interpret a patient's symptoms, a patient may think
he is having a heart attack while his doctor believes he just has
heartburn. Differences in global metaphysical or political worldviews
(naturalism, theism, liberalism, marxism) may also generate different
beliefs about particulars on a more comprehensive scale.
Relations to other inquirers. People may stand in different epistemic
relations to other inquirers—for example, as informants, interlocutors,
students—which affects their access to relevant information and their
ability to convey their beliefs to others.
These kinds of situatedness affect knowledge in several ways. They
influence knowers' access to information and the terms in which they
represent what they know. They bear on the form of their knowledge
(articulate/implicit, formal/informal, by acquaintance or description,
and so forth). They affect their attitudes toward their beliefs
(certainty/doubt, dogmatic/open to revision), their standards of
justification (relative weights they give to different epistemic values
such as predictive power and consilience, amount, sources, and kinds of
evidence they require before they accept a claim, etc.), and the
authority with which they lay claim to their beliefs and can offer them
to others. Finally, they affect knowers' assessment of which claims are
significant or important.
Social situation. Many of these ways in which knowers' physical and
psychological relations to the world affects what and how they know are
familiar and extensively studied by cognitive psychology, naturalized
epistemology, and philosophy of science. Feminist epistemology takes
such studies a further step by considering how the social location of
the knower affects what and how she knows. It can thus be seen as a
branch of social epistemology. An individual's social locations
consists of her ascribed social identities (gender, race, sexual
orientation, ethnicity, caste, kinship status, etc.) and social roles
and relationships (occupation, political party membership, etc.).
Partly in virtue of their different ascribed identities, individuals
occupy different social roles that accord them different powers,
duties, and role-given goals and interests. They are subject to
different norms that prescribe different virtues, habits, emotions, and
skills that are thought to be appropriate for these roles. They also
acquire different subjective identities. Subjective identification with
one's social groups can take several forms. One may simply know oneself
to have certain ascribed identities. One may accept or endorse these
identities, actively affirming the norms and roles associated with
them. Or one may regard one's social identities as oppressive (if, say,
one's identity is cast by society as evil, contemptible, or
disgusting), yet see one's fate as tied with the groups with which one
is identified, and commit oneself to collective action with other
members of those groups to overcome that oppression.
Gender as a mode of social situation. Most feminist theorists
distinguish between sex and gender. Sex comprises the biological
differences between males and females. Gender is what societies make of
sexual differences: the different roles, norms, and meanings they
assign to men and women and the things associated with them on account
of their real or imagined sexual characteristics. Gender thus has
several dimensions (Haslanger 2000).
Gender roles. Men and women are assigned to distinct social roles. For
example, most societies reserve political and military offices mostly
for men, and assign women most childrearing responsibilities.
Gender norms. Men and women are expected to comply with different norms
of behavior and bodily comportment. For example, men are expected to be
assertive and athletic; women, deferential and modest. Gender norms are
tailored to gender roles: men and women are expected to conform to
those norms that make them fit for their gender roles (whether or not
they actually occupy those roles).
Gendered traits and virtues. Psychological traits are considered
“masculine” and “feminine” if they dispose their bearers to comply with
the gender norms assigned to men and women, respectively. “Masculine”
traits are therefore regarded as virtues in men and (often) vices in
women, while “feminine” traits are regarded as vices in men and virtues
in women.
Gendered performance/behavior. Many feminist theorists, often
influenced by postmodernism, have come to stress the contextual and
performative aspects of gender (West & Zimmerman 1987; Butler
1990). Rather than viewing masculinity and femininity as fixed traits,
expressed in every social context, these theorists represent human
beings as more flexible and disposed to enact both “masculine” and
“feminine” behaviors in different contexts. The man who avoids tenderly
comforting a crying baby in the presence of women may do so when alone.
Rather than viewing masculinity and femininity as manifested only in
behavior within fixed, distinct gender roles, they can be seen as
contrasting styles of performance in almost any role. Female body
builders strive to show off their muscles in a “feminine” way.
Gender identity. A person's ascribed gender identity—how others
identify him or her—may not match his or her subjective gender
identity—the sense that one is “really” a man or a woman. Subjective
gender identity includes all of the ways one might understand oneself
to be a man or a woman. One could identify with any subset of gender
norms, roles, and traits ascribed to the gender of which one sees
oneself as a member, while repudiating others. One could even repudiate
them all, but still identify oneself as a man or a women in terms of
what one sees as distinct roles men and women ought to play in bringing
about a just future (one that may or may not include gender
distinctions). One could, as many feminists do, understand one's gender
identity as a predicament shared by all with the same ascribed
identity, and thus as a basis for collective action to change the very
basis of one's gender identity. One could embrace an “androcentric”
identity, including both “feminine” and “masculine” roles, norms, and
traits, decline to view oneself in gender polarized terms at all, or
play with gender identities in a postmodernist spirit.
Gender symbolism. Animals and inanimate objects may be placed in a
gendered field of representation through conventional association,
imaginative projection, and metaphorical thinking. Thus, the garage is
regarded as “male” space, the kitchen, “female”; male deer are said to
have “harems”; pears are seen as “womanly”, assault rifles as “manly.”
Gendered knowledge. By bringing together the general account of
situated knowledge with the account of gender as a kind of social
situation, we can now generate a catalogue of ways in which what people
know, or think they know, can be influenced by their own gender (roles,
norms, traits, performance, identities), other people's genders, or by
ideas about gender (symbolism). Each mode of gendered knowledge raises
new questions for epistemology.
The phenomenology of gendered bodies. People's bodies are not just
differently sexed; they are differently gendered. Early child
socialization trains boys' and girls' bodies to different norms of
bodily comportment. In the U.S., these norms stress physical freedom,
aggressive play, large motor skills, informal and relaxed posture, and
indifference to clothing, neatness and appearance in boys; physical
constraint, subdued play, small motor skills, formal and modest
posture, and self-consciousness about clothing, neatness and appearance
for girls. Once internalized, such norms profoundly affect the
phenomenology of embodiment. They inform men's and women's distinct
first-personal knowledge of what it is like to inhabit a body, to
express capacities unique to one sex or another (e.g., breast feeding),
and to have experiences that are manifested through different body
parts in differently sexed bodies (e.g., orgasm). They also cause men's
and women's experiences of gendered behaviors that both can perform to
differ—in comfort, fluidity, feelings of “naturalness” or novelty,
self-consciousness, confidence, awkwardness, shame, and so forth. One
question these facts raise for feminist epistemology is to what extent
dominant models of the world, especially of the relation between minds
and bodies, have seemed compelling because they conform to a male or
masculine phenomenology (Bordo 1987; Young 1990).
Gendered first-personal knowledge de se. It is one thing to know what
sexual harassment is, and how to identify it in a case described in
third-personal terms. It is another to come to the recognition “I have
been sexually harassed.” Many women who are able to see that women in
general are disadvantaged have difficulty recognizing themselves as
sharing women's predicament (Clayton & Crosby 1992). The problems
of de se knowledge are particularly pressing for feminist theory,
because it is committed to theorizing in ways that women can use to
improve their lives. This entails that women be able to recognize
themselves and their lives in feminist accounts of women's predicament.
Feminist epistemology is therefore particularly concerned with
investigating the conditions of feminist self-understanding and the
social settings in which it may arise—feminist consciousness-raising
sessions, women's studies classes, and so forth (MacKinnon 1989).
Gendered emotions, attitudes, interests, and values. Feminist theory
defines a representation as androcentric if it depicts the world in
relation to male or masculine interests, emotions, attitudes or values.
A “male” interest is an interest a man has, in virtue of the goals
given to him by social roles that are designated as especially
appropriate for men to occupy, or in virtue of his subjective gender
identity. A “masculine” interest is an interest a man has in virtue of
attitudes or psychological dispositions that are thought specifically
appropriate to men. Such attitudes and interests structure the
cognition of those who have them. For example, a representational
scheme that classifies women as either “babes,” “dogs,” “whores,” or
(grand)mothers reflects the androcentric attitudes, interests, and
values of single heterosexual adolescent men who view women in terms of
their fantasized eligibility for sexual intercourse with them. A
representation is gynocentric if it depicts the world in relation to
female or feminine interests, emotions, attitudes or values. When a man
is described as an “eligible bachelor,” this reflects the gynocentric
perspective of a heterosexual, single woman interested in marriage. An
interest, emotion, attitude, or value might be symbolically gendered
even if men and women do not manifest it differently. For example the
ethics of care represents moral problems in terms of symbolically
feminine values—values culturally associated with women's gender roles
(Gilligan 1982). It thus can qualify as a symbolically gynocentric
perspective, even if men and women do not differ in their propensity to
represent moral problems in its terms, and are equally able to act
accordingly. From a performative perspective, this shows that men can
behave in “feminine” ways, too. Feminist epistemology raises numerous
questions about these phenomena. Can situated emotional responses to
things be a valid source of knowledge about them (Diamond 1991, Jaggar
1989, Keller 1983)? Do dominant practices and conceptions of science
and scientific method reflect an androcentric perspective, or a
perspective that reflects other dominant positions, as of race and
colonial rule (Merchant 1980; Harding 1986, 1991, 1993, 1998)? Do
mainstream philosophical conceptions of objectivity, knowledge, and
reason reflect an androcentric perspective (Bordo 1987; Code 1991; Flax
1983; Rooney 1991)? How would the conceptual frameworks of particular
sciences change if they reflected women's interests (Anderson 1995b,
Waring 1990)?
Knowledge of others in gendered relationships. Gender norms
differentially structure the social spaces to which men and women are
admitted, as well as the presentation of self to others. As
performative theories of gender stress, men manifest their male
identity, and women their female identity, differently alone than in
mixed company, and differently in these settings than in
gender-segregated contexts. Male and female inquirers therefore have
access to different information about others. Male and female
ethnographers may be admitted to different social spaces. Even when
admitted to the same social spaces, their presence has different
effects on those being observed, because they do not stand in the same
social relationships to their subjects. Physical objects do not behave
differently depending on whether a man or a woman is observing them.
But human beings do behave differently according to their beliefs about
the gender of who is observing them. Research that elicits information
about others through personal contact between the researchers and the
research subjects therefore raises the question of how findings might
be influenced by the gendered relations between researchers and
subjects, and whether gender-inclusive research teams are in a better
position to detect this. Ethnography, which derives propositional
knowledge of others from personal knowledge of native informants in
long-term, often intimate relationships, raises these issues most
acutely (Bell et al 1993; Leacocke 1981). Similar issues arise in
survey research, clinical research, and human experimentation (Sherif
1987).
Gendered skills. Some skills are labelled masculine or feminine because
men and women need them specifically to perform their respective gender
roles, and they are not generically useful for almost any role (as
walking, talking, and seeing are). It takes a particular knowledge of
small children to know how to comfort them, a particular knowledge of
soldiers to know how to whip up their morale. Although men and women
alike may acquire and exercise these skills, they are considered the
peculiar responsibility of one or the other gender. Men and women may
therefore have differential access to such skill-based knowledge. To
the extent that the skill is perceived by the agent as the proper
province of the “other” gender, he or she may have a difficult time
seeing himself or herself perform it confidently and fluidly, and this
inability to self-identify with the task can impair performance. The
feedback effects of the phenomenology of gendered embodiment and de se
knowledge of one's own subjective gender identity can therefore
influence the exercise of gendered skills. To the extent that a skill
is perceived by others as the proper province of one gender, others may
grant or withhold acknowledgment of an agent's expertise. If the
successful exercise of the skill requires that others be willing to
accept it as a competent performance—as in the cases of comforting
children or raising soldiers' morale—others' gender-based readiness or
refusal to grant expertise to an agent in exercising that skill can be
a self-fulfilling prophecy. These phenomena raise various questions for
epistemology. Does the “masculine” symbolism of certain scientific
skills, such as of assuming an “objective” stance toward nature,
interfere with the integration of women into science? Do actually or
symbolically “feminine” skills aid the acquisition of scientific
knowledge (Keller 1983, 1985a; Rose 1987; Smith 1974)?
Gendered cognitive styles. Some theorists believe that men and women
have different cognitive styles (Belenky et al 1986; Gilligan 1982).
Whether or not this is true, cognitive styles are gender symbolized
(Rooney 1991). Deductive, analytic, atomistic, acontextual, and
quantitative cognitive styles are labelled “masculine,” while
intuitive, synthetic, holistic, contextual and qualitative cognitive
styles are labelled “feminine.” Such associations are not wholly
arbitrary, the way blue is gendered male and pink, female. For example,
it is seen as masculine to make one's point by means of argument,
feminine to make one's point by means of narrative. Argument is
commonly cast as an adversarial mode of discourse, in which one side
claims vindication by vanquishing the opposition. Such pursuit of
dominance follows the competitive pattern of male gender roles in
combat, athletics, and business. Narrative is a seductive mode of
discourse, persuading by an enticing invitation to take up the
perspective of the narrator, which excites one's imagination and
feeling. Its operations are more like love than war, and thereby
follows a mode of persuasion thought more suitable for women. These
phenomena raise numerous epistemological questions: does the quest for
“masculine” prestige by using “masculine” methods distort practices of
knowledge acquisition (Addelson 1983; Moulton, 1983)? Are some kinds of
sound research unfairly ignored because of their association with
“feminine” cognitive styles (Keller 1983, 1985b)? Do “feminine”
cognitive styles yield knowledge that is inaccessible or harder to
achieve by “masculine” means (Duran 1991, Rose 1987, Smith 1974)?
Gendered background beliefs and worldviews. We have seen above how men
and women have access to different phenomenological knowledge, de se
knowledge, know-how, and personal knowledge of others, in virtue of
their gender. They also tend to represent the world in different terms,
in virtue of their gendered interests, attitudes, emotions and values,
and perhaps also (although this is a matter of controversy among
feminist theorists) in virtue of different cognitive styles. These
differences create different background webs of belief against which
information to which men and women have in principle equal access may
be processed. Representational schemes that are functional for
different gender roles and gendered attitudes make different kinds of
information salient. In traditional domestic settings, women tend to
notice dirt that men don't. This is not because women have a specially
sensitive sensory apparatus. It is because they have a role which
designates the females of the household as the ones who have to clean
up. Male surgeons have no difficulty maintaining much higher degrees of
vigilance about contamination in an operating room than would ever be
warranted in housecleaning. Besides making different kinds of
information salient to men and women, their different background
knowledge may lead them to interpret commonly accessed information
differently. A man might read a woman's demure smile as a coy come-on,
where another woman may interpret it as her polite and defensive
reaction to unwanted attention from him. Such differences can spring
from differential access to phenomenological knowledge. The male and
female observers imaginatively project themselves into her situation,
inferring her feelings from the feelings they think underlie her body
language. Because men's and women's phenomenologies of embodiment are
different—most men are not in the habit of smiling as a defense against
unwanted attention from women—the man may narcissistically imagine the
smile as relaxed and spontaneous, whereas the woman may suspect it is
forced. Here are a few epistemological questions raised by these
phenomena. Are there epistemic obstacles to men's ability to know when
they are raping or sexually harassing women, or to legal institutions
recognizing this, insofar as they confine their thinking within a
“masculine” perspective (MacKinnon 1989)? More generally, do the
unexamined sexist or androcentric background beliefs of scientists
cause them to generate sexist theories about women, despite their
adherence to ostensibly objective scientific methods (Harding 1986;
Harding & O'Barr, 1987; Hubbard 1990)? More generally still, how
might the social practices of science be organized so that variations
in background beliefs of inquirers function as a resource rather than
an obstacle to scientific success (Longino 1990; Solomon 2001)?
Relations to other inquirers. Gender differences in knowledge and
background beliefs can be reduced if men and women participate in
inquiry together. Each gender can take on testimony what the other can
acquire through direct experience. Each may also learn how to exercise
imaginative projection more effectively, and to take up the perspective
of the other gender. However, gender norms influence the terms on which
men and women communicate (Kalbfleisch 1995). In many contexts, women
are not allowed to speak or even show up, or their questions, comments,
and challenges are ignored, interrupted, and systematically distorted,
or they aren't accepted as experts. Gendered norms of conversational
interaction and epistemic authority thus influence the ability of
knowledge practices to incorporate the knowledge and experience of men
and women into their processes of discovery and justification. Feminist
epistemologists are therefore interested in exploring how gender norms
distort the dissemination of testimony and relations of cognitive
authority among inquirers (Addelson 1983; Code 1991) and how the social
relations of inquirers could be reformed, especially with regard to the
allocation of epistemic authority, so as to enable more successful
practices of inquiry (Longino 1990; Nelson 1990, 1993).
Problems of and Approaches to Gendered Situated Knowledge. Mainstream
epistemology takes as paradigms of knowledge simple propositional
knowledge about matters in principle equally accessible to anyone with
basic cognitive and sensory apparatus: “2 + 2=4”; “grass is green”;
“water quenches thirst.” Feminist epistemology does not claim that such
knowledge is gendered. But examination of such examples is not
particularly helpful for answering the epistemological problems that
arise specifically in feminist theory and practice. What is it to know
that I am a woman? What is it like to be sexually objectified? Why is
it that men and women so often have dramatically divergent
understandings of what happened in their sexual encounters? How can we
arrange scientific practices so that science and technology serve
women's interests? These kinds of questions make other kinds of
knowledge salient for feminist epistemology: phenomenological
knowledge, de se knowledge, knowledge of persons, know-how, moral
knowledge, knowledge informed by emotions, attitudes, and interests.
These kinds of knowledge are often gendered, and they can influence the
propositional claims people are disposed to form and accept. This has
critical implications for mainstream epistemological conceptions of
knowledge, insofar as the latter are based on false generalizations
drawing only from examples of ungendered knowledge.
Feminist epistemologists stress the situatedness or
perspective-relativity of much knowledge. They do not thereby embrace
epistemological relativism. To regard some knowledge claim or form of
understanding as situated in a perspective is not to claim that the
perspective yields true beliefs or satisfactory understandings (not
even “for” those taking up the perspective). It is not to claim that
perspectives can only be judged in their own terms, nor that no
perspectives are better than others, nor that one cannot take a more
objective view of the phenomena than that taken up in one or another
perspective. It is not to claim that all knowledge necessarily reflects
some peculiar non-universalizable relation of a subset of knowers to
the object of knowledge. What attention to situated knowledge does do
is enable questions to be raised and addressed that are difficult even
to frame in epistemologies that simply assume that gender, and the
social situation of the knower more generally, is irrelevant to
knowledge. How are the knowledge claims generated by gendered
perspectives related to one another? Can men take up a gynocentric
perspective, and women, an androcentric perspective? Or are there
epistemological barriers to such perspective crossing? Are certain
perspectives epistemically privileged? Is there any way to construct a
more objective perspective out of differently gendered perspectives?
What is the relation of an objective perspective, if one is possible,
to gendered perspectives? What would be the point of achieving such a
perspective? Would the achievement of such an objective perspective
make possible or desirable the elimination of gendered perspectives?
Feminist epistemology does not rule out in advance the possibility or
desirability of objective knowledge. It does raise new questions about
objectivity.
Feminist epistemologists have developed their approaches to the
situatedness of knowledge within three broad epistemological
traditions: standpoint theory, postmodernism, and empiricism.
Standpoint theory identifies one particular social situation as
epistemically privileged. Postmodernism rejects claims of epistemic
privilege, emphasizing instead the contingency and instability of the
social identity of knowers, and consequently of their representations.
Empiricism seeks standards, within a naturalized framework, for
differentiating the circumstances in which situatedness generates error
and in which it constitutes a resource that can be harnessed to advance
knowledge. It advances a conception of objectivity constituted by
critical and cooperative relations among a plurality of differently
situated inquirers.
2. Feminist Standpoint Theory
Standpoint Epistemology in General. Standpoint theories claim to
represent the world from a particular socially situated perspective
that can lay a claim to epistemic privilege or authority. A complete
standpoint theory must specify (i) the social location of the
privileged perspective, (ii) the scope of its privilege: what questions
or subject matters it can claim a privilege over, (iii) the aspect of
the social location that generates superior knowledge: for example,
social role, or subjective identity; (iv) the ground of its privilege:
what it is about that aspect that justifies a claim to privilege; (v)
the type of epistemic superiority it claims: for example, greater
accuracy, or greater ability to represent fundamental truths; (vi) the
other perspectives relative to which it claims epistemic superiority
and (vii) modes of access to that perspective: is occupying the social
location necessary or sufficient for getting access to the perspective?
Many claims to epistemic privilege on behalf of particular perspectives
with respect to certain questions are commonplace and uncontroversial.
Auto mechanics are generally in a better position than auto consumers
to know what is wrong with their cars. Practical experience in
fulfilling the social role of the mechanic grounds the mechanic's
epistemic privilege, which lays a claim to greater reliability than the
judgments of auto consumers.
Standpoint theories become controversial when they claim epistemic
privilege over socially and politically contested topics on behalf of
the perspectives of systematically disadvantaged social groups,
relative to the perspectives of the groups that dominate them. The
scope of the claimed privilege includes the character, causes, and
consequences of the social inequalities that define the groups in
question. This type of standpoint theory classically claims three types
of epistemic privilege over the standpoint of dominant groups: First,
it claims to offer deep over surface knowledge of society: the
standpoint of the disadvantaged reveals the fundamental regularities
that drive the phenomena in question, whereas the standpoint of the
privileged captures only surface regularities. Second, in virtue of
this, it claims to offer superior knowledge of the modality of surface
regularities, and thus superior knowledge of human potentialities.
Where the standpoint of the privileged tends to represent existing
social inequalities as natural and necessary, the standpoint of the
disadvantaged correctly represents them as socially contingent, and
shows how they could be overcome. Third, it claims to offer a
representation of the social world in relation to universal human
interests. By contrast, the standpoint of the privileged represents
social phenomena only in relation to the interests of the privileged
class, but ideologically misrepresents these interests as coinciding
with universal human interests.
Marxist Standpoint Theory. Marxism offers the classic model of a
standpoint theory, claiming an epistemic privilege over fundamental
questions of economics, sociology, and history on behalf of the
standpoint of the proletariat (Marx 1964, Lukács 1971). Workers
do not have this standpoint to begin with. They attain it by gaining
collective consciousness of their role in the capitalist system and in
history. Several aspects of workers' social situation enable them to
attain an epistemically privileged perspective on society. Workers are
oppressed, central to the capitalist mode of production, endowed with a
cognitive style based on their practical productive material
interaction with nature, and collectively self-conscious agents of a
potentially universal class. Oppression gives them an objective
interest in the truth about whose interests really get served by the
capitalist system. Centrality gives them experiential access to the
fundamental relations of capitalist production. Because, under
capitalism, the standing of all other classes is defined in relation to
them, in coming to know themselves and their class position, workers
come to know their society as a totality (Lukács 1971).
Practical productive interaction with the world is the fundamental mode
by which people come to know it, in a materialist epistemology. It
leads workers to represent their world in terms of use values, whereas
capitalists represent it in terms of exchange values. The workers'
representation is more fundamental, because the basic laws of economics
and history are expressed in terms of the struggle over the
appropriation of surplus (use-) value, not in terms of superficial
money (exchange) values. The necessary and transhistorical character of
this practical, instrumental mode of knowing also gives it an objective
validity for all societies, which must come to grips with accounting
for surplus value in terms of ultimate use-values. Universality—the
workers' standing as the agents for the future universal class they
will become under communism (where everyone has the same class status,
standing in a common relation to the means of production as both
workers and collective rulers over the surplus)—entails that workers
represent the social world in relation to universal human interests,
rather than in relation to class-specific interests (as is true of
capitalist perspectives). This gives their representations of society
greater objectivity than capitalist representations. Finally, the
collective self-consciousness of the workers has, as all successful
intentional action does, the character of a self-fulfilling prophecy.
Workers' collective insight into their common predicament and the need
to overcome it through collective revolutionary action generates a
self-understanding which, when acted upon, gets realized. Workers
become the universal class, the primary agent of history, by acting on
that self-understanding. The epistemic privilege of the standpoint of
the proletariat, therefore, is also grounded in the epistemic privilege
that autonomous agents have over what they are doing.
Grounds of Feminist Standpoint Theory. Feminist standpoint theory
claims an epistemic privilege over the character of gender relations,
and of social and psychological phenomena in which gender is
implicated, on behalf of the standpoint of women. The privilege is
relative to theories that justify patriarchy or reflect sexist
assumptions. Various feminist standpoint theories ground the claim to
epistemic privilege in different features of women's social situation.
Each can be seen as drawing an analogy with one or more strands of
Marxist epistemology.
Centrality. According to marxist feminists, such as Hartsock (1987) and
Rose (1987) women are central to the system of reproduction—of
socializing children and caring for bodies—as workers are central to
the system of commodity production. Because women are in charge of
tending to the needs of everyone else in the household, they are in a
better position than men to see how patriarchy fails to meet people's
needs. Men, in virtue of their dominant position, have the privilege of
ignoring how their actions undermine the interests of subordinates. The
epistemic privilege of women therefore rests on the fact that women as
a class have superior access to information about whose needs get
better served under patriarchy.
Collective self-consciousness. According to MacKinnon (1999) male
dominance is based on sexual objectification, a process involving
epistemic mystification. In objectification, dominant groups project
their desires onto subordinate groups and, in virtue of their power,
make subordinate groups conform to the way dominants want them to be.
It represents as given, natural, and necessary the group differences
that are caused by dominant group desires. Gender is the mode of
objectification constituted by erotic desire, the eroticization of
domination. Men constitute women as women by representing their natures
as essentially sexually subordinate to men and treating them
accordingly. Women can unmask these ideological misrepresentations by
achieving and acting on a shared understanding of themselves as
women—that is, as a social group unjustly constituted by sexual
objectification. Women act collectively on this shared understanding in
resisting the sexist representations made of them, through campaigns
against sexual harassment, pornography, restrictions on reproductive
freedom, and so forth. Through these feminist actions, in which women
refuse to act as sexual objects, women show that representations of
women as sexual objects are not natural or necessary. Their privileged
knowledge is agent self-knowledge, made true by being put into action.
Cognitive style. Many versions of standpoint theory (including Flax
1983, Hartsock 1987, Rose 1987, and Smith 1974) accept feminist object
relations theory, which explains the development of stereotypical
feminine and masculine traits in terms of the different problems of
identity-formation faced by male and female children who are raised by
female caregivers (Chodorow 1978). Object relations theory postulates
that male children form their distinctive masculine identities by
separating themselves from their mothers, a task that psychologically
involves an anxious rejection of the feminine and a continuous need to
maintain distance and boundaries by controlling and denigrating the
feminine. Female children gain a sense of their gender identity through
identification with their mothers, and so are more comfortable with a
blurring of boundaries between self and other. The development of
gender identities leads males and females to acquire distinctively
masculine and feminine cognitive styles. The masculine cognitive style
is abstract, theoretical, disembodied, emotionally detached,
analytical, deductive, quantitative, atomistic, and oriented toward
values of control or domination. The feminine cognitive style is
concrete, practical, embodied, emotionally engaged, synthetic,
intuitive, qualitative, relational, and oriented toward values of care.
These cognitive styles are reinforced through the distinctive types of
labor assigned to men and women—men having a near monopoly on the
theoretical sciences, warmaking, and on positions of political and
economic power calling for detachment and control; and women being
assigned to hands-on emotional care for others. The feminine cognitive
style is said to be epistemically superior because it overcomes the
dichotomy between the subject and object of knowing and because an
ethics of care is superior to an ethics of domination. Ways of knowing
informed by the motive of caring for everyone's needs will produce more
valuable representations than ways of knowing informed by the interests
of the dominant (Hartsock 1987). They will produce representations of
the world in relation to universal human interests, rather than in
terms of the interests of dominant classes, ideologically
misrepresented as universal interests. To institutionalize the feminine
way of knowing, however, would require overcoming the division of
mental, manual, and caring labor that characterizes capitalist
patriarchy (Rose 1987).
Oppression. Women are oppressed, and therefore have an interest in
representing social phenomena in ways that reveal rather than mask this
truth. They also have direct experience of their oppression, unlike
men, whose privilege enables them to ignore how their actions affect
women as a class. The logic of an epistemology that grounds epistemic
privilege in oppression is to identify the multiply oppressed as
multiply epistemically privileged. Within feminist theory, this logic
has led to the development of black feminist epistemology. Collins
(1990) grounds black feminist epistemology in black women's personal
experiences of racism and sexism, and in cognitive styles associated
with black women. She uses this epistemology to supply black women with
self-representations that enable them to resist the demeaning racist
and sexist images of black women in the wider world, and to take pride
in their identities. The epistemic privilege of the oppressed is
sometimes cast, following W.E.B. DuBois, in terms of “bifurcated
consciousness”: the ability to see things both from the perspective of
the dominant and from the perspective of the oppressed, and therefore
to comparatively evaluate both perspectives (Harding 1991, Smith 1974,
Collins 1990). Black women are “outsiders within,” having enough
personal experience as insiders to know their social order, but enough
critical distance to empower critique.
Access to the Feminist Standpoint. Every standpoint theory must offer
an account of how one gains access to its situated knowledge. This
depends on whether membership in the group whose perspective is
privileged is defined objectively, in terms of one's position in a
social structure, or subjectively, in terms of one's subjective
identification as a member of the group. When group membership is
defined objectively, it is neither necessary nor sufficient for gaining
access to the privileged perspective. It is not sufficient, because one
might be unaware of the fact or objective significance of being a
member of the group. Members become aware of their objective group
identity only by achieving a shared understanding of their predicament
with other group members. This is the function of consciousness-raising
groups in feminist practice (MacKinnon 1999). It is not necessary,
because when a group is defined objectively, the facts that constitute
the group as such and its interests are publicly accessible, so anyone
can theorize phenomena in relation to the interests of that group.
Thus, Marx theorized from the standpoint of the proletariat, even
though he was not a worker. However, to the extent that the ground of
epistemic privilege lies in the self-knowledge of autonomous agents,
only those who participate in that agency can have first-personal agent
knowledge. At this point, the site of epistemic privilege shifts from
the group as defined objectively to the group defining itself as a
collective political agent. The privileged standpoint is not that of
women, but of feminists. Men can participate in the feminist movement,
too. But they cannot assume a dominant role in defining (hence knowing)
the aims of the feminist movement without defeating that movement,
given that a constitutive aim of feminism is overcoming male dominance.
When group membership is defined subjectively, then membership in the
group is both necessary and sufficient to gain access to the
perspective of the group. If subjectively identifying as a woman is
necessary and sufficient to have a feminine cognitive style, as
object-relations theory postulates, then all and only self-identified
woman have access to the epistemically privileged standpoint.
Similarly, Collins' (1990) version of black feminist epistemology rests
on identity politics.
Goals of Feminist Standpoint Theory. Feminist standpoint theory is a
type of critical theory, as this term was understood by the Frankfurt
school of critical social theorists, from Adorno to Habermas. Critical
theories aim to empower the oppressed to improve their situation. They
therefore incorporate pragmatic constraints on theories of the social
world. To serve their critical aim, social theories must (a) represent
the social world in relation to the interests of the oppressed—i.e.,
those who are the subjects of study; (b) supply an account of that
world which is accessible to the subjects of study, which enables them
to understand their problems; and (c) supply an account of the world
which is usable by the subjects to study to improve their condition.
Critical theory is theory of, by, and for the subjects of study. These
pragmatic features of critical theory raise the possibility that claims
of superiority for particular theories might be based more on pragmatic
than epistemological virtues (Harding 1991, Hartsock 1996). Even if a
particular feminist theory cannot make good on the claim that it has
privileged access to reality, it may offer true representations that
are more useful to women than other truthful representations.
Criticisms of Feminist Standpoint Theory. Longino (1993b) argues that
standpoint theory cannot provide a noncircular basis for deciding which
standpoints have epistemic privilege. Bar On (1993) argues against
grounding women's epistemic privilege in their oppression, via feminine
cognitive styles. If the feminine ethics of care provides the
epistemically privileged perspective on morality, then our access to
moral knowledge is predicated on the continuation of existing gender
relations, which produce this ethic. Grounding epistemic privilege in
feminine cognitive styles therefore forces a choice between having
ethical knowledge and living in a nonsexist society. Bar On also claims
that the center-periphery model that underwrites the epistemic
privilege of workers does not apply to women. Marx held that class
conflict is the central phenomenon that drives all other forms of group
conflict, including sexism, racism, imperialism, and national and
religious conflict. So understanding class could yield an understanding
of other dimensions of inequality. It is no longer plausible to hold
that any group inequality is central to all the others; they intersect
in complex ways (Crenshaw 1999). This entails that women cannot even
have privileged access to understanding their own oppression, since
this takes different forms for different women, depending on their
race, sexual orientation, and so forth. This critique has been
forcefully developed by feminist postmodernists, who question the very
possibility of a unified standpoint of women, and see, behind the
assertion of a universal woman's viewpoint, only the perspective of
relatively privileged white women (Lugones & Spelman 1983).
3. Feminist Postmodernism
General Postmodernist Themes. Postmodernism as a North American
intellectual movement draws inspiration from a variety of French
poststructuralist and postmodernist theorists, including Foucault,
Lacan, Derrida, Lyotard, and Irigaray. It embodies a skeptical
sensibility that questions attempts to transcend our situatedness by
appeal to such ideas as universality, necessity, objectivity,
rationality, essence, unity, totality, foundations, and ultimate Truth
and Reality. It stresses the locality, partiality, contingency,
instability, uncertainty, ambiguity and essential contestability of any
particular account of the world, the self, and the good. Politically,
the postmodernist emphasis on revealing the situatedness and
contestability of any particular claim or system of thought is supposed
to serve both critical and liberatory functions. It delegitimizes ideas
that dominate and exclude by undermining their claims to transcendent
justification. And it opens up space for imagining alternative
possibilities that were obscured by those claims.
Although postmodernist themes are often expressed in an obscure jargon,
they can be cast in terms more familiar to analytic philosophers.
Postmodernists begin with ideas about language and systems of thought.
They claim that (what we think of as) reality is “discursively
constructed.” This is the linguistic version of the now inescapable (!)
Kantian thought that our minds grasp things not as they are “in
themselves” but only through concepts, signified by words. “The
linguistic sign acts reflexively, not referentially” in a “discursive
field.” This is a version of radical meaning holism: signs get their
meaning not from their reference to external things but from their
relations to all of the other signs in a system of discourse. Meaning
holism entails that the introduction of new signs (or elimination of
old ones) will change the meanings of the signs that were already in
use. Signs therefore do not have a fixed meaning over time. This is a
Heraclitean version of historicism: we cannot step into the same stream
of thought twice. Together, these ideas support the “rejection of
totalizing metanarratives.” There can be no complete, unified theory of
the world that captures the whole truth about it. Any such theory will
contain a definite set of terms. This entails that it cannot express
all conceptual possibilities. For a discourse that contained different
terms would contain meanings not available in the discursive field of
the theory that claims completeness. Thus, the selection of any
particular theory or narrative is an exercise of “power”—to exclude
certain possibilities from thought and to authorize others.
Postmodernism extends these ideas about language to social practices
more generally. The key idea underwriting this extension is that
actions and practices are linguistic signs. Like words, they signify
things beyond themselves by means of linguistic devices such as
metaphor and metonymy. For example, the elevation of the judge's bench
metaphorically signifies his superior authority over everyone else in
the courtroom. This permits an analysis of social practices and
behaviors as exhibiting the same structure and dynamics as language
itself. Just as words get their meaning from their relations to other
words rather than from their relation to some external reality, so do
actions get their meaning from their relations to other actions, rather
than from their relation to some pre-linguistic realm of human nature
or natural law. Thus, the superior authority of the judge consists in
the conventions of deference others manifest in their actions toward
him. It is not underwritten by a supposed natural tendency of humans to
obey authority, or by an underlying normatively objective authority.
The latter thoughts express essentialist and objectivist power plays,
attempts to foreclose contests over practices by fixing them in a
supposedly extra-linguistic reality. Such attempts are not only
objectionable but futile, because the meanings of actions are
constantly being subverted by other actions that, in changing the
context of the former actions, changes their meanings. This is why
postmodernists celebrate ironic, parodic, and campy renditions of
conventional behaviors as politically liberating (Butler 1993). If Marx
lamented that history repeats itself twice—first as tragedy, second as
farce—postmodernists revel in the same process.
Postmodernists view the self as likewise constituted by signs that have
meaning only in relation to other signs. There is no unified self that
underlies the play of a stream of signifiers. This is a linguistic
version of Hume's fragmented stream-of-consciousness account of the
self, but with a social twist. Signs, unlike Hume's simple ideas, form
language, which is socially constructed. Thus, although subjectivity is
constituted through the production of signs, the self is not free to
make of these whatever it wants, but finds itself entangled in a web of
meanings not of its own creation. Our identities are socially imposed,
not autonomously created. However, this does not foreclose the
possibility of agency, because we occupy multiple social identities
(e.g., a woman might be a worker, a mother, lesbian, Mexican, and so
forth). The tensions among these conflicting identities open up spaces
for disrupting the discursive systems that construct us.
Because, in its philosophy of language, words refer to concepts rather
than things in the world, postmodernism reproduces in linguistic terms
some of the same epistemological conundrums posed in the history of
modern philosophy by the veil of ideas. This generates a tendency
toward idealism in both traditions. However, given the constant flux of
meanings generated by holism, these tendencies cannot secure the
certainty or stability that empiricists thought they could attain by
resorting to idealism. The more careful practitioners of postmodernism
resist wholesale idealism. Claims that bodies, matter, or the objects
investigated by the natural sciences are “discursively constructed” or
“socially constructed” do not assert that the external world would
disappear if people stopped talking about it. Rather, they assert a
kind of nominalism: that the world does not dictate the categories we
use to describe it, that innumerable incompatible ways of classifying
the world are available to us, and therefore that the selection of any
one theory is a choice that cannot be justified by appeal to
“objective” truth or reality. Even the ways we draw our distinctions
between mind and body, ideas and objects, discourse and reality, are
contestable.
Feminist Postmodernism. Within feminism, postmodernist ideas have been
deployed against theories that purport to justify sexist
practices—notably, ideologies that claim that observed differences
between men and women are natural and necessary, or that women have an
essence that explains and justifies their subordination. The oft-cited
claim that gender is socially or discursively constructed—that it is an
effect of social practices and systems of meaning that can be
disrupted—finds one of its homes in postmodernism (Butler 1990).
However, postmodernism has figured more prominently in internal
critiques of feminist theories. One of the most important trends in
feminist thinking in the past twenty years has been exposing and
responding to exclusionary tendencies within feminism itself. Women of
color and lesbian women have argued that mainstream feminist theories
have ignored their distinct problems and perspectives (Collins 1990;
Hull, Scott and Smith, 1982; Lorde 1984). Feminist postmodernism
represents both a vehicle for and response to these critiques. It
underwrites a critique of the concept “woman”—the central analytical
category of feminist theory. And it proposes perspective-shifting as a
strategy for negotiating the proliferation of theories produced by
differently situated women.
The critique of the concept “woman.” Feminist postmodernists have
criticized many of the leading feminist theories of gender and
patriarchy as essentialist (Butler 1990, Flax 1990, Spelman 1988).
Essentialism here refers to any theory that claims to identify a
universal, transhistorical, necessary cause or constitution of gender
identity or patriarchy. The objection to essentialism is fundamentally
political: in claiming that gender identity is one thing or has one
cause, such theories convert discursively constructed facts into norms,
difference into deviance. They either exclude women who don't conform
to the theory from the class of true “women,” or else represent them as
inferior. The critiques of feminist theories by lesbian women and women
of color have reinforced skepticism about the unity presumed in the
category “woman” by highlighting the intersectionality of identities of
gender, race, class, and sexual orientation. The chief faultlines for
the fragmentation of the category “woman” have thus been the other
identity formations along which social inequalities are constructed.
This critique of “woman” as a unified object of theorizing entails that
“woman” also cannot constitute a unified subject of knowing (Lugones
& Spelman 1983). The theories of universal gender identity under
attack are ones in which the authors, all white middle class
heterosexual women, could see themselves. Critics claim that the
authors fail to acknowledge their own situatedness and hence the ways
they are implicated in and reproduce power relations—in this case, the
presumptuous authority of white middle class heterosexual women to
define “the standpoint of women”—to speak for all other women and
define who they are. Feminist standpoint theorists, who claim an
epistemic privilege on behalf of their standpoint, are thereby unmasked
as asserting a race and class privilege over other women.
Feminist postmodernists draw two lessons from this critique. First,
universal claims about women, gender, and patriarchy should be avoided.
Second, feminist standpoint theory's project of identifying a single
epistemically privileged perspective is fundamentally flawed, an
unjustified assertion of power in the name of an unattainable
objectivity. This lesson applies to subaltern feminist standpoints as
well. The assertion of a black feminist standpoint, for example,
objectionably essentializes black women. Once the postmodernist
critique of essentialism is granted, there is no logical stopping point
in the proliferation of perspectives.
Perspective shifting. Feminist postmodernism thus envisions our
epistemic situation as characterized by a permanent plurality of
perspectives, none of which can claim objectivity—that is,
transcendence of situatedness to a “view from nowhere.” This position
has sometimes been characterized as relativist. Haraway (1991) replies
that it rejects both objectivism and relativism for the ways they let
knowers escape responsibility for the representations they construct.
To claim objectivity for a representation is to claim that “the world
made me represent things this way.” To claim relativism is to claim
that “my identity (my situation) made me represent things this way (and
my identity/situation is not inferior to yours).” Both positions
disclaim the active participation of the knower in constructing her
representations. Even a photograph, the paradigm of an “objective”
representation, reflects the photographer's choice of film, lenses,
frames, exposure, and so forth. But the resort to a relativism of
identity is no better. In asserting the equality of all perspectives,
it claims immunity from the critiques of differently positioned others,
and complacency in one's own position. Although it acknowledges the
dependence of a knower's representations on the particulars of her
situation, it claims that she had no choice about that. Postmodernists,
however, reject the fixity and unity of personal identity on which
relativism rests. People are not epistemically trapped inside their
cultures, their gender, their race, or any other identity. They can
choose to think from other perspectives. Thus, although we will always
have a plurality of perspectives, their constitution is constantly
shifting rather than static, and there is no stable correspondence
between individuals and perspectives.
Negotiating the bewildering array of situated knowledges therefore
involves two types of epistemic practice. One is acceptance of
responsibility, which involves acknowledging the choices of situation
that entered into the construction of one's representations (Haraway
1991), and considering how one's situation affects the content of one's
representations (Harding 1993). The second is “world traveling”
(Lugones 1987) or “mobile positioning”—trying to see things from many
other perspectives. Mobile positioning can never be transparent or
innocent. Imagining oneself in another's situation is full of risks. It
requires sensitive engagement with and sympathy for the others who
occupy those positions. Both transform situated knowing into a critical
and responsible practice.
Criticisms of Feminist Postmodernism. Both key features of feminist
postmodernism—the rejection of “woman” as a category of analysis, and
the infinite fragmentation of perspectives—are controversial within
feminist theory. A wholesale opposition to large-scale generalizations
about women seems to arbitrarily preclude a critical analysis of
large-scale social forces that critically affect women (Benhabib 1995).
That women in different social positions may experience sexism
differently does not entail that they have nothing in common—they still
suffer from sexism (MacKinnon 2000). Intersectionality, rather than
being a basis for dissolving the category “woman,” may be accommodated
through a structural analysis of gender that allows for racialized and
otherwise particularized modes of sexist oppression (Haslanger 2000).
The postmodernist alternative of fragmentation and multiplicity
threatens both the possibility of analytical focus (it is impossible to
keep all axes of difference in play at once) and of politically
effective coalition building among women with different identities.
Carried to its logical conclusion, feminist postmodernism dissolves all
groups, thereby reproducing the individualism of the Enlightenment
epistemology it claims to repudiate. And the idea of mobile positioning
may simply reproduce the objectivism and ideas of autonomy that
postmodernists claim to reject, only now in the guise of “the view from
everywhere” rather than “the view from nowhere” (Bordo 1990). Critics
argue that feminists would do better if they forthrightly appropriated
ideals of human rights and autonomy, rather than embracing “the death
of the subject” in the fragmentation of the self (Benhabib 1995).
Despite these difficulties, postmodernism remains a powerful current in
feminist epistemology, due to the acknowledgment by all feminists that
a plurality of situated knowledges appears to be an inescapable
consequence of social differentiation and embodiment.
4. Feminist Empiricism
Relations of Feminist Empiricism to Empiricism in general. Empiricism
is the view that experience provides the sole, or at least the primary,
justification for all knowledge. From the classical empiricists to some
early twentieth-century theorists, empiricists held that the content of
experience could be described in fixed, basic, theory-neutral terms—for
example, in terms of sense-data. Most also regarded philosophy as a
discipline that could provide a transcendent or external justification
for empirical or scientific methods. Quine revolutionized empiricism by
rejecting both of these ideas. For Quine, observation is thoroughly
theory-laden. It is cast in terms of complex concepts that cannot be
immediately given in experience, all of which are potentially subject
to revision in light of further experience (Quine 1963). And
epistemology, far from providing an extrascientific vindication of
natural science, is simply another project within science, in which we
empirically investigate our own practices of inquiry (Quine 1969). In
these two respects, feminist empiricists are the daughters of Quine.
However, Quine accepted a sharp division between facts and values that
feminist empiricists argue cannot be sustained within a thoroughly
naturalized empiricism. Feminist empiricists are deeply engaged in
considering how feminist values can legitimately inform empirical
inquiry, and how scientific methods can be improved in light of
feminist demonstrations of sex bias in currently accepted methods.
Their version of naturalized epistemology therefore does not follow
Quine in reducing epistemology to nonnormative psychological
investigations, but rather upholds the roles of value judgments in
rigorous empirical inquiry (Campbell 1998, Nelson 1990). Quine also
presupposes an individualist account of inquiry; his preferred
reduction basis for naturalized epistemology is behavioral and neuro-
psychology. Feminist empiricists are concerned with the impact on
inquiry of social practices relating to gender, race, class and other
bases of inequality. They therefore take sociology, history, and
science studies seriously. Most also advocate a socialized
epistemology, in which inquiry is treated as a fundamentally social
process and the basic subjects of knowledge may even be communities or
networks of individuals.
The Paradoxes of Bias and Social Construction. The central problematics
of feminist empiricism can be captured in two apparent paradoxes.
First, much feminist science criticism consists in exposing the
androcentric and sexist biases in scientific research, especially in
theories about women, sexuality, and gender differences. The force of
this criticism seems to rest on a prior empiricist commitment to the
view that bias is epistemically bad—that it leads to false theories.
Yet, advocates of feminist science urge that feminist values inform
scientific inquiry. This amounts to a recommendation that science
incorporate certain biases into its operations. Feminist empiricists
need to reconcile these conflicting claims. This is known as the
paradox of bias. Second, and relatedly, much feminist science criticism
is devoted to exposing the influence of social and political factors on
scientific inquiry. Scientists advocate androcentric and sexist
theories because they are influenced by the sexist values of the wider
society. This would seem to imply that, to eliminate these social
biases, feminists adopt an individualist epistemology. Instead,
feminist epistemologists stress the social construction of knowledge.
They urge, not that inquirers insulate themselves from social
influences, but that they restructure scientific practices to be open
to different social influences. This can be called the paradox of
social construction.
Feminist empiricists argue that the key to dissolving both paradoxes is
to undermine the assumptions that underlie them: that biases, political
values, and social factors can influence inquiry only by displacing the
influence of evidence, logic, and whatever other purely cognitive
factors tend to lead to true theories. Not all bias is epistemically
bad (Antony 1993). There are three general strategies for showing this,
which may be called pragmatic, procedural, and moral realist. The
pragmatic approach stresses the plurality of aims that inquiry serves.
Inquiry seeks truths, or at least empirically adequate representations,
but which truths any particular inquiry seeks depends on the uses to
which those representations will be put, many of which are practical
and derived from social interests. The paradoxes are dissolved by
showing how responsible inquiry respects a division of labor between
the functions of evidence and social values—the evidence helping
inquirers track the truth, the social values helping inquirers
construct representations out of those truths that serve the pragmatic
aims of inquiry (Anderson 1995b). This view may be joined with a view
of nature as rich, complex, and messy. No single theory captures the
whole structure of reality, since different ways of classifying
phenomena will reveal different patterns useful to different practical
interests (Longino 2001). The procedural approach argues that
epistemically bad biases can be kept in check through an appropriate
social organization of inquiry. A social organization that holds people
with different biases accountable to one another will be able to weed
out bad biases, even if no individual on her own can be free of bias
(Longino 1990). This view may be joined with the idea that the subject
of knowledge (Nelson 1993), epistemic rationality (Solomon 2001) or
objectivity (Longino 1990, 2001) is the epistemic community, not the
individual. The moral realist approach argues that moral, social and
political value judgments have truth-values, and that feminist values
are true. Inquiry informed by feminist values therefore does not
displace attention to the evidence, because the evidence vindicates
these values (Campbell 1998).
Feminist empiricists appeal to the pragmatist tradition to undermine
the sharp dichotomy between fact and value (Antony 1993; Nelson 1993).
They argue (compatibly with other pragmatists, such as Hilary Putnam),
that Quine's arguments about the underdetermination of theory by
evidence lead to a view of facts as partially constituted by values,
and values by facts. In the absence of a sharp distinction between
facts and values, it cannot be argued that inquiry explicitly motivated
by feminist values is in principle opposed to the truth. Whether any
particular feminist, or sexist, theory is true or false will depend on
empirical investigation informed by epistemic norms—norms which may
themselves be reformed in light of the merits of the theories they
generate. This is the project of naturalized epistemology, whereby the
vindication of norms of inquiry is sought not outside, but within,
ordinary empirical investigation. Feminist empiricist investigations of
the interaction of facts and values are further discussed below.
Feminist empiricist explorations of how norms of inquiry should be
constituted to enhance objectivity are also discussed below.
Criticisms of Feminist Empiricism. Within feminist theory, the
intellectual traditions and training of standpoint and postmodernist
epistemologists have not kept track of the radical changes in the
empiricist tradition inspired by Quine and further developed by
feminist empiricists. Consequently, some criticisms of what is called
“feminist empiricism” by other feminist theorists do not fit what
feminists who call themselves “feminist empiricists” believe. For
example, feminist postmodernists criticize feminist empiricists for
presuming the existence of an individual, transhistorical subject of
knowledge outside of social determination (Harding 1990), even though
the naturalized epistemology that feminist empiricists adopt has long
since abandoned that conception of knowers in favor of viewing knowers
as socially situated. Feminist empiricists are also criticized for
accepting an uncritical concept of experience (Scott 1991), even though
feminist empiricists accept the theory- and value-laden character of
evidence and hence the critical revisability of descriptions of
experience in light of new evidence, theoretical, and normative
reflections. Feminist empiricists have also been criticized for naively
holding that that science will correct the errors and biases in its
theories about women and other subordinated groups all by itself,
without the aid of feminist values or insights (Harding 1986, 1991).
This contrasts with the actual position of those who call themselves
feminist empiricists, who argue that science cannot claim to attain
objective knowledge of gendered beings or our gendered social world
without actively including feminist inquirers as equals in the
collective project of inquiry (Longino 1993a, 1993b). More pointedly,
the standpoint theorist Hundleby (1997) criticizes feminist empiricism
for overlooking the vital role of feminist political activity, in
particular, the development of oppositional consciousness, as a
superior source of hypotheses and evidence for challenging sexist and
androcentric theories.
5. Feminist Science Criticism and Feminist Science
The history of feminist interventions into most disciplines follows a
common pattern. Feminist inquiry begins as a critique of accepted
disciplinary methods, assumptions, and canons. As it matures, it
develops constructive projects of its own. The history of feminism and
science follows this pattern. In the empirical sciences, the pattern
helps us see how feminist epistemology negotiates the tension between
the two poles in the paradox of bias that lies at the core of the
feminist empiricist project. Feminist science critics focus on
identifying androcentric and sexist biases in the actual practice of
science. This practice began by representing bias as a source of error.
But as philosophers and historians of science joined the practice of
feminist science criticism, they developed a more sophisticated way of
understanding some biases as epistemic resources. Advocates of feminist
science develop this theme in seeking to practice science in light of
and in the service of feminist aims and values. They thereby represent
feminist biases as epistemic resources.
Feminist Science Criticism: Bias as Error. Feminist science criticism
originated in the critiques that working biologists, psychologists, and
other scientists made of the androcentric and sexist biases and
practices in their own disciplines—especially of theories about women
and gender differences that legitimate sexist practices. Exemplary
works in this tradition include Bleier (1984), Fausto-Sterling (1985),
Hrdy (1981), Leacock (1981), Sherif (1987), and Tavris (1992). The
criticism takes many forms. (1) Studies of how the exclusion or
marginalization of women scientists impair scientific progress. For
example, the failure to provide Barbara McClintock with professional
standing, resources, and access to graduate students delayed
incorporation of her pioneering discoveries of genetic transposition
into mainstream biology (Keller 1983). (2) Studies of how the
applications of science and technology disadvantage women and other
vulnerable groups, treat their interests as less important, or express
contempt for them. Examples include eugenics (Hubbard 1990), and
economic development policies that reinforce gender hierarchy by
offering training and resources to men, but not women, in developing
countries (Waring 1990). Such practical ill-effects of science
applications can be traced in part to epistemic defects in the
underlying science—to bogus concepts of race in the case of eugenics,
and to failures to recognize women's work as contributing to the
“economy” in the case of sexist development policies. (3) Studies of
how science has ignored women and gender, and how turning attention to
these issues may require revisions of accepted theories. Hays-Gilpin
and Whitley (1998) document particularly dramatic examples of this in
the field of archaeology. (4) Studies of how biases toward working with
“masculine” cognitive styles—for example, toward centralized,
hierarchical control models of causation as opposed to “feminine”
(contextual, interactive, diffused) models—have impaired scientific
understanding, for example, in studies of slime-mold (Keller 1985b) and
molecular biology (Spanier 1995). (5) Studies of how research into sex
differences and women's and men's “natures” that reinforces sex
stereotypes and sexist practices fail to live up to standards of good
science—for example, in drawing inferences on the basis of miniscule
sample sizes or correlations not tested against an appropriately
designed control group, or in ignoring disconfirming data (
Fausto-Sterling 1985, Tavris 1992). Gender bias may also be revealed in
the conceptual framework of the theory in question—for example, in
representing subjective gender identification as a dichotomous
variable, thereby eliminating other possibilities, such as androgyny,
from consideration (Bem 1993).
In all of these cases, gender bias is represented as a cause of error,
or at least delay in recognizing the truth. But, as philosophers and
historians of science joined the practice of feminist science
criticism, alternative models of gender bias were developed, sometimes
in cooperation with working scientists. Exemplary works of feminist
science criticism by philosophers and historians of science include
Haraway (1989), Harding (1986, 1991, 1993, 1998), Lloyd (1993), Longino
& Doell (1983), Schiebinger (1989), and Wylie (1996). Although some
of this work is devoted to exposing errors caused by sexist and
androcentric bias, some of it is devoted rather to showing how the
interests in technological control that underlie the modern practice of
science limit its scope and what it takes to be significant knowledge
(Lacey 1999, Merchant 1980, Tiles 1987). Another core project of
feminist science criticism is demonstrating that the evidence assembled
on behalf of the theories under study does not compel assent to the
theories. The theories go well beyond the data that support them, with
the gap being filled by sexist and androcentric assumptions. Thus,
Haraway (1989) uses the tools of literary theory to demonstrate how
hypotheses in primatology and evolutionary theory depend on narrative
conventions (for example, casting the transition from ape to hominid as
a heroic drama) and tropes (for example, casting primates as mirrors of
human nature). While these narrative conventions and tropes have
considerable persuasive power, their appeal is rhetorical, and the
evidence does not compel their selection. Beyond this negative
critique, feminist science critics are interested in uncovering and
defending the viability of alternative nonsexist and feminist theories
of the phenomena in question. When they operate in this mode, the
critics are not claiming that sexist and androcentric theories are
false, but rather that they are not proven or established, because at
this stage in the development of the evidence, legitimate and at least
equally viable rivals exist.
To sort out these different accounts of the cognitive role of gender
bias, it is helpful to distinguish four dimensions in the evaluation of
research programs: (1) conceptual criticism; (2) methodological
criticism; (3) evaluating the relation of the available evidence to the
program's hypotheses (does the evidence tend to confirm or disconfirm
them?); (4) comparing the program's theory to rival theories in terms
of their empirical adequacy and other epistemic values. Bias in a
research program is revealed as error to the extent that it is shown to
generate or rest on (1) confused or nonreferring concepts that purport
to refer (for example, the concept of “race” as biological subspecies
of human beings); (2) violation of valid methodological principles; (3)
belief in a theory in the face of a lack of evidential support for it,
or strong evidence against it; or (4) continued commitment to a theory
with some evidential support, even when some rival theories dominate it
with respect to all epistemic values, including empirical adequacy.
Biases shown to generate error in this way should be stopped, through
better training of scientists or the adoption and enforcement of
methodological principles designed to check their influence. Feminist
science criticism in the bias-as-error mode parallels the
heuristics-and-biases tradition of psychology (Kahneman, Slovic and
Tversky 1982), a tradition which has already been taken up in
naturalized epistemology and philosophy of science (e.g., Solomon
2001). On a normative level, it generates methodological principles for
engaging in nonsexist science. Exemplary normative (methodological)
works generated by feminist science criticism include Altmann (1974)
and Eichler (1988).
Bias in a research program is shown to be limiting or partial, but not
necessarily erroneous, to the extent that avoids clear error and
generates (1) a limited range of concepts and/or (2) uses a limited
range of methods, (3) has some empirical successes, while (4) rival
theories, depending on different concepts and/or methods, can also
claim to avoid clear error and to possess some empirical successes or
other epistemic virtues not possessed by the research program in
question. Such biases are legitimate: it is rationally acceptable to
conduct scientific inquiry under the influence of such biases. Indeed,
empirical investigations into the workings of the human mind strongly
suggest that we have no choice but to think in accordance with some
biases (Chomsky has shown, for example, that we have innate ideas of
deep grammatical structures). Moreover, the underdetermination of
theory by data implies that without some biases, we would be unable to
make sense of our world at all (Antony 1993). When biases are partial
but not clearly erroneous, they serve a positive generative function:
they produce new concepts, methods, and hypotheses that open up new
aspects of the world for understanding. They are resources for
enhancing our grasp of the world. From a normative point of view,
feminist philosophers of science argue that we have an epistemic
interest in ensuring that certain limiting biases do not dominate
research to the exclusion of other generative biases that would
generate rival theories possessing a different range of important
empirical successes. The point in exposing the androcentric and sexist
biases lying behind certain research theories is not to show that they
are false (they might in the end be empirically vindicated), but to
make salient the room for alternative programs not based on such biases.
Feminist Science: Bias as Resource. Most advocates of feminist science
argue, in this vein, that scientific inquiries informed by feminist
values are based on legitimate, generative limiting biases. They argue
not that feminist sciences should exclude other ways of doing science,
but that feminist sciences should be included as among the legitimate
choices available to investigators. This picture of science is
pluralistic, compatible with the postmodern rejection of “totalizing
narratives,” but more inclined than postmodernists to explain the
persistence of pluralism in the social and applied sciences in
scientific realist terms: science is disunified because the world is
rich with a multitude of cross-cutting structures, which no single
theoretical vocabulary can capture. Different communities have
interests in different aspects of reality, so leaving them free to
follow their interests will reveal different patterns and structures in
the world (Harding 1998; Longino 2001).
Against this pluralistic view, some advocates of feminist science
define it in terms of adherence to specific ontologies and
methodologies expressing a “feminine” cognitive style (Duran 1991,
Keller 1983, 1985a). On this conception, for example, the content of
any feminist theory should have a relational rather than an atomistic
ontology, favor the concrete over the abstract, avoid generalizations
about women in favor of exposing the richness and particularity of
different women's lives and perspectives, and so forth. Its methods
should encompass intuition, emotional engagement, and other cognitive
styles associated with a feminine sensibility. This view has had
perhaps its greatest impact in feminist works attacking quantitative
methods in the social sciences. For example, Stanley & Wise (1983)
argue that only qualitative methods that accept women's reports of
their experiences in their own terms, refusing to generalize, can
uphold feminist values of respecting differences among women and
avoiding the replication of power differences between researchers and
research subjects.
Pluralist feminist scientists and philosophers of science have
vigorously contested these attempts to define feminist science in terms
preferred content and “feminine” method. They argue that many questions
of interest to feminists are best answered with quantitative methods
(Jayaratne & Stewart, 1991), and indeed that feminists may properly
make use of a wide range of methods (Harding 1987, Nielsen 1990,
Reinharz 1992). Feminist science is not defined by its content, but
rather by the pragmatic interests that generate the questions it asks.
(Sometimes this distinction is cast as one between “feminist science”
and “doing science as a feminist.”) Feminists are interested in
uncovering the causes of women's oppression, revealing the dynamics of
gender in society, and producing knowledge that women can use to
overcome the disadvantages to which they are subject. Forms of
knowledge that simply valorize the “feminine” may not be helpful to
women who would be better off not having norms of femininity imposed on
them. In any event, feminist pluralists argue that advocates of
“feminine” science have not shown that feminine cognitive styles and
ontologies are, as a general matter, better able to track the truth
(Longino 1989).
If feminist science amounts to “doing science as a feminist”—that is,
using science to answer questions generated by feminist interests—one
may ask whether it differs in any substantive respect from the science
that is already practiced by nonfeminists. Feminist pluralists reply
that scientific practice is already highly disunified; philosophies of
the special sciences reveal great variations in methods, background
assumptions, sources of evidence, cognitive values, and interpretive
strategies (Longino 2001). So the dichotomy between feminist and
mainstream science presupposed by the question is false. Doing biology,
primatology, anthropology, archaeology, psychology, economics, history
or any other special science as a feminist—that is, with the aim of
answering feminist questions—has resulted in many and various local
methodological innovations, discoveries of new sources of evidence, and
developments of alternative theories (see, for example, Bell, Caplan
and Karim 1993; Haraway 1989; Hays-Gilpin and Whitley 1998; Nielsen
1990). These are then made available to inquirers asking other,
nonfeminist questions. Thus, there is no presumption that certain
methods, evidence, etc. are uniquely available to serve feminist
cognitive interests.
Nevertheless, there are some common threads in “doing science as a
feminist” that tend to favor certain types of representation over
others (Longino 1994). Feminists are interested in epistemic practices
that reveal the operations of gender in the world, and opportunities
for women to resist and transform these operations. One way gender bias
operates to reinforce sexism is through the perpetuation of
categorical, dichotomous thinking which represents masculinity and
femininity as “opposites,” femininity as inferiority, and nonconformity
to gender norms as deviant. This gives feminists an interest in the
value of “ontological heterogeneity”—using categories that permit the
observation of within-group variation and that resist the
representation of difference from the group mean as a form of deviance.
Gender bias also reinforces sexism through single-factor causal models
that attribute seemingly intrinsic powers to men by neglecting their
wider context. The value of “complexity of relationship” favors the
development of causal models that facilitate the representation of
features of the social context that support male power, including
female participation and complicity. Other feminist cognitive values
involve the accessibility of knowledge: feminist favor knowledge that
“diffuses power” in being cast in a form usable to people in
subordinate positions, who usually lack technical expertise and access
to expensive equipment. This interest underlies the appropriate
technology movement in developing countries. For similar reasons,
feminists are more interested in knowledge applicable to meeting human
needs than in research programs with little prospect of advancing these
interests. These values are feminist in the sense of advancing feminist
interests, but their usefulness is not confined to feminism. None of
these feminist cognitive values displace or compete with the search for
truth, because doing science as a feminist, like doing science with any
other interest in mind (for example, medical or military interests)
involves commitment to the cognitive value of producing empirically
adequate theories.
6. Feminist Defenses of Value-Laden Inquiry
The Challenge of Value-Neutrality. The theory and practice of feminist
science raises the question of how any inquiry shaped by moral, social,
and political interests can simultaneously be faithful to the
fundamental epistemic interest in truth. Against the project of
feminist science, many philosophers hold that true science is neutral
among social, moral, and political values. Lacey (1999) usefully
distinguishes the following claims of value-neutrality: (1) Autonomy:
science progresses best when uninfluenced by social/political movements
and values. (2) Neutrality: scientific theories do not imply or
presuppose any judgments about noncognitive values, nor do scientific
theories serve any particular noncognitive values more fully than
others. (3) Impartiality: The only grounds for accepting a theory are
its relations to the evidence. These grounds are impartial among rival
noncognitive values.
Of these claims, neutrality is the most dubious, because it depicts the
grounds for accepting social, political and moral values as utterly
detached from evidence about human potentialities and about what
happens when people try to realize these values in practice. If this
were true, then the defenders of keeping mathematics a male preserve
would not have bothered arguing that women were not intellectually
capable of doing mathematics and that their uteri would wander if they
tried to do it—and feminists would not have bothered disputing those
claims. Neutrality is less a claim about the character of science than
about the justification of social and political values. As a
categorical claim about the latter, it is false. Taylor (1985) and
Tiles & Oberdiek (1995) show, in detailed case studies, how
scientific theories do serve some social and political values more than
others.
The core claim of value-neutrality, however, is impartiality. The
thought that underwrites impartiality is that scientific theories aim
at the truth, at what is the case, whereas value judgments deal with
what ought to be the case. Even if neutrality is false, because facts
constitute part of the warrant for value judgments, the converse is not
true. Only facts can supply the warrant for other facts. Autonomy, in
turn, is defended as a means to ensure that science satisfies the
demands of impartiality. Social and political movements are thought to
threaten autonomy because their primary influence on science is thought
to consist in pressuring scientists to ignore the facts and validate
their worldviews. Defenders of impartiality object to the very idea of
feminist science because they view it as threatening impartiality.
The Basic Underdetermination Argument. Feminist empiricists reply to
the challenge of value-neutrality by extending Quine's argument that
theory is underdetermined by evidence (Longino 1990, Nelson 1993). Any
body of observations counts as evidence for particular hypotheses only
in conjunction with certain background assumptions. Vary the background
assumptions, and the same observations will support quite different
hypotheses. For example, the failure to observe stellar parallax in the
17th century was taken as evidence that the Earth stands still by
geocentrists, and as evidence that the stars are very far away by
heliocentrists. No logical principle stops scientists from choosing
different background assumptions against which to interpret their
observations. In practice, scientists face some constraints in the
selection of background assumptions, based on cognitive values such as
simplicity and conservatism (resistance to revising deeply entrenched
assumptions on which many other beliefs depend). But these cognitive
values rarely reduce the scope for choice down to one option, and their
interpretation and weights are contestable in any event (geocentrism
was overturned only by overriding conservatism). Feminist empiricists
conclude that, given the scope for choice in background assumptions,
nothing stops scientists from selecting their background assumptions on
account of their fit with social and political values, or indeed any
other preference or interest. It follows that feminist scientists may
select their background assumptions on account of their fit with
feminist values.
Putnam (1981) has advanced a similar argument, carried to feminist
conclusions by Nelson (1993). Value judgments operate like factual
judgments in the web of belief, such that values judgments figure in
the background assumptions that support factual judgments, and
vice-versa. If the web of belief integrates judgments of fact and of
value, then there is no clear distinction between these two judgment
types. So there is no good argument against permitting feminist values
to shape scientific judgments.
The underdetermination argument pries open a potential space for social
values in science. But it is not sufficient to demonstrate the
legitimacy of any particular ways of introducing feminist values into
science. Feminist science critics and feminist scientists agree that
there are cognitively illegitimate as well as cognitively legitimate
ways for social values to influence science. That is the basis for
distinguishing error-generating biases from biases that serve as
cognitive resources, a distinction required to dissolve the paradox of
bias. Standing alone, the underdetermination argument does not help us
discriminate one from the other. Additional criteria are needed.
One lesson about what to look for can be drawn from earlier debates
over the theory-ladenness of observation. It is now generally agreed
that the theory-laden character of observations does not threaten their
status as evidence for a theory, provided that the theories presupposed
in those observations do not immediately include the very theory being
tested by those observations. Circularity, at least of a narrow sort,
should be avoided. Similarly, the chief danger of value-laden inquiry
is a kind of circularity of wishful thinking. The value-laden character
of the background assumptions linking evidence to theories should not
foreclose the possibility of discovering that one's values are
mistaken, because based on erroneous beliefs about human potentialities
and the consequences of putting certain values into practice. (Notice
that it makes sense to worry about the danger of wishful thinking only
if the neutrality thesis is false.) If women really can't do math, or
their uteri really do migrate when they try (causing hysteria, as the
sexist theory held), the values incorporated into feminist science
should not close off this possibility in advance. Although, in setting
out to test these sexist hypotheses, women scientists presuppose their
own mathematical competence, this does not preclude their discovering
otherwise. They need only open their calculations to public criticism
to keep this possibility alive. If their evidence disconfirms the
sexist hypotheses, and their calculations survive public scrutiny, then
they have not run a vicious circle.
The Basic Pragmatic Strategy. The above reflections provide a standard
for determining when socially value-laden inquiry has gone wrong. But
they do not explain what positive epistemic influence they could have.
How could they function as an epistemic resource? Feminist
epistemologists at this point stress the pragmatic functions of inquiry
(Anderson 1995b). All inquiry begins with a question. Questions may be
motivated not only by the purely cognitive interest of curiosity, but
by various practical interests in understanding the nature and causes
of situations one judges to be problematic, and in finding out how to
improve those situations. The resulting product of inquiry—a theory or
set of systematically connected beliefs—should therefore be shaped to
these practical-cum-cognitive interests. The pragmatic aspects of
inquiry introduce new dimensions of evaluation to theories. We can ask
not only whether the theories are backed by sufficient evidence to
warrant their acceptance, but whether they are cast in forms that are
cognitively accessible to the situated knowers who want to use these
theories, whether they are useful to these knowers (help them solve
their problems), and whether they answer the questions they were
designed to answer. A set of statements can be true, yet fail these
pragmatic tests.
Even the staunchest defenders of the value-neutrality of science
acknowledge that pragmatic factors legitimately influence the choice of
objects of study. In this function, then, pragmatic interests,
including social and political values, are epistemic resources:
inquirers with different interests will study and make discoveries
about different aspects of the world. But the defenders of
value-neutral science contend that once inquirers decide where to cast
their flashlight, what gets lit up is determined entirely by the nature
of the world. Feminist epistemologists argue that the light of
practical interests penetrates more deeply into what is discovered than
this. Knowers (subjects) play a more active role in constituting the
object of knowledge than the flashlight metaphor suggests. (This is one
thing feminist epistemologists mean when they say they reject “the
subject-object dichotomy”.) “Constitution” has two senses,
representational and causal. In the representational sense, knowers
constitute the object of knowledge in choosing the terms in which they
represent it, and in defining the context in which it is represented as
operating. If knowing is like seeing, all seeing is a form of “seeing
as”—and different interests will make us see the “same” things
differently (Longino 1990). This is a straightforward implication of
the fact of situated knowing. In the causal sense, some representations
have a causal impact on what is represented. When what we are
representing is ourselves, uptake of our self-representations will
change who we are and what we do. This follows from our agency, which
is the determination to govern ourselves by our self-understandings.
This is sometimes what is meant by the claim that subjects, or their
identities, are “socially constructed.”
The basic pragmatic strategy for defending feminist science, or any
inquiry shaped by social and political values, is to show how the
pragmatic interests of that inquiry license or require a particular
mode of influence of values on the process, product, and uptake of the
product of inquiry, while at the same time leaving appropriate room for
evidence to play its warranting role. Values and evidence play
different, cooperative roles in properly conducted inquiry; values do
not compete with evidence for the determination of belief (Anderson
1995b).
A Catalogue of Types of Legitimate Influence of Social Values in
Science. One can examine the actual operation of particular values in
particular scientific investigations and judge, on a case by case
basis, whether the values are closing off the possibility of
discovering unwelcome facts, leading scientists to reason in a vicious
circle, or insulating their findings from critical scrutiny, or whether
the values are enabling the discovery of new facts—whether they are, in
short, obstructing or facilitating the search for knowledge. Such
judgments are contextual and subject to revision in light of new
evidence. What follows is a catalogue of types of influence of social
values that feminist epistemologists and philosophers of science have
argued may in principle legitimately influence theory choice (although
whether their influence is epistemically good or bad in a particular
case requires further investigation).
Selection and weighting of cognitive values. Kuhn (1977) argued that
scientists need to appeal to cognitive values to take up the slack
between theory and evidence. His list of cognitive values included
accuracy (empirical adequacy or truth), scope, simplicity,
fruitfulness, internal consistency and consistency with other beliefs
(conservatism). As we have seen above, Longino (1994) argues that
feminists have reason to prefer theories that manifest other cognitive
values, such as diffusion of power. Diffusion of power, like
simplicity, is not a truth-oriented cognitive value. Both count as
cognitive values because they make theories cognitively accessible,
comprehensible to our finite minds. Diffusion of power recognizes that
cognitive accessibility is relative to the situation of the knower.
(Longino's characterization of other values of feminist science, such
as ontological heterogeneity and complexity of relationship, as
“cognitive” values is something of a misnomer—these fit better under
the rubrics of classification and models, below.) Both simplification
and diffusion of power stand in tension with truth, in that theories
that embody them not only ignore many complex, messy truths, but may
even make false claims. Whether this is bad depends on whether the
truths ignored or the inaccuracies embraced are important, and this can
be judged only in relation to the interests of the investigator. All
legitimate research programs must seek to incorporate the value of
empirical adequacy, which requires at least that theories try to
approximate the truth. But how much accuracy this requires depends on
how much the expected usefulness of the knowledge will be compromised
by larger margins of error. The situation and pragmatic interests of
the inquirer or of the potential users of a theory may therefore
legitimately affect the selection and weighting of cognitive values in
theory choice.
Standards of Proof. By convention, social scientists reject the null
hypothesis (that observed results in a statistical study reflect mere
chance variation in the sample) only for P-values < 5%, an arbitrary
level of statistical significance. Bayesians and others argue that the
level of statistical significance should vary, depending on the
relative costs of type I error (believing something false) and type II
error (failing to believe something true). In medicine, clinical trials
are routinely stopped and results accepted as genuine notwithstanding
much higher P-values, if the results are dramatic enough and the
estimated costs to patients of not acting on them are considered high
enough. (The cost of not providing a potentially effective treatment
may be death, while the cost of providing a useless treatment may be
small.) This practice explicitly incorporates social value judgments in
the standard of proof required before results are accepted. Hare-Mustin
and Maracek (1994) argue, by parallel reasoning, that whether studies
that find gender differences, or that fail to find them, should be
accepted depends on the relative costs of Alpha Bias (exaggerating
differences) and Beta Bias (neglecting differences) in the context at
hand.
Classification. The ways observed phenomena are classified may
legitimately depend on the values of the researcher. In medicine, the
distinction between health and disease reflects moral judgments about
human welfare and appropriate ways of dealing with problems, as well as
judgments about causation. A condition regarded as bad for human beings
is not classified as a disease unless some kind of medical therapy is
considered both an appropriate and a potentially effective way to deal
with it. Feminist inquiries, too, raise questions about the causes of
women's oppression that require classifying phenomena as instances of
rape, sexual objectification, sex discrimination, and so
forth—classifications all tied to their meeting both empirical and
evaluative criteria (Anderson 1995a, 1995b).
Methods. The methods selected for investigating phenomena depend on the
questions one asks and the kinds of knowledge one seeks, both of which
may reflect the social interests of the investigator. Experimental
methods in social science may be good for discovering factors that can
be used to control people's behavior in similar settings. But to grasp
their behavior as action—that is, as attempts by agents to govern their
behavior through their self-understandings—requires different empirical
methods, including qualitative interviews (which allow subjects to
delineate their own systems of meaning) and participant observation.
Standpoint theories, as critical theories, aim as well at empowering
the subjects of study by helping them forge liberatory
self-understandings, and these, too, may require different methods of
inquiry—for example, consciousness-raising (MacKinnon 1999).
Causal Explanations; Explanations of Meaning; Narratives. For most
phenomena, the number of factors that have a causal impact on their
occurrence is vast—too large to comprehend or test in a single model.
Investigators must therefore select a subset of causal factors to
include in the models they test. This selection may be based on
considerations of cost or availability—some types of data are hard or
expensive to get; cheap and accessible methods may be better suited to
testing the causal influence of some variables than others. The
selection of causal variables may also be based on fit with the social
or personal interests of the investigator (Longino 1990, 2001). These
interests often reflect background social and moral judgments of blame,
responsibility, and acceptability of change. To take an innocuous case,
in most contexts, what is singled out as a cause of dangerous fires is
a spark, flame, or flammable material, not the presence of oxygen. The
items judged possible to change, or worth changing, are the focus of
causal explanation. To take a more controversial case, conservatives
are more likely to study divorce and out-of-wedlock birth as causes of
women's poverty, whereas feminists are more likely to focus on other
causes—for example, the exclusion of women from better-paid jobs, the
weak bargaining power of women in marriage, and norms of masculinity
that induce fathers to avoid significant participation in
child-rearing, thereby forcing women to forego earnings in taking up
the slack. Notice that these causal explanations are not incompatible.
All the causal factors cited may contribute to the feminization of
poverty.
Often what inquirers seek is not merely a set of facts, but what the
facts mean. Meaning holism implies that the meaning or significance of
facts depends on their relations to other facts. Even if two inquirers
agree on the causal facts, they may still disagree about their meaning
because they relate the facts in different ways, reflecting their
background values. Feminists may agree with conservatives that divorce
is a cause of the feminization of poverty, but deny that this means
that women are better off married. They argue that marriage itself,
with its gendered division of domestic and market labor, constitutes
one of the major structural disadvantages women face, setting them up
for worse outcomes in the event of divorce (Okin 1989). Conservatives,
viewing marriage as an indispensable condition of the good life, are no
more willing to view marriage in this light than most people would be
willing to blame oxygen for the occurrence of house fires. It might be
thought that scientists should stick to the facts and avoid judgments
of meaning. But most of the questions we ask demand answers that fit
facts into larger, meaningful patterns. Scientists therefore cannot
help but tell stories, which require the selection of narrative
frameworks that necessarily go beyond the facts (Haraway 1989). This
selection may depend both on their fit with the facts and on their fit
with the background values of the storyteller.
Framework Assumptions. As we ascend to higher levels of abstraction,
very general framework assumptions come into play in constituting the
object of study. Some of these are disciplinary. Economics studies
humans as self-interested, instrumentally rational choosers. Social
psychology studies humans as responding to socially meaningful
situations. Behaviorism studies humans as controlled by objectively
defined environmental variables. Behavioral genetics studies humans as
controlled by their genes. These are all forms of “seeing as.” Longino
(1990) and Tiles (1987) argue that the selection of framework
assumptions may depend on their fit with the interests of the inquirer.
Feminists are interested in promoting women's agency, so they tend to
prefer frameworks that permit the representation of women as agents.
This selection does not guarantee that they will confirm the background
assumption that women are agents. Causal models that include only
agentic variables may not explain much of the variation in women's
behavior; models that include both agentic and nonagentic variables may
find that the latter explain all of the variation. The value-laden
selection of framework assumptions need not lead to a vicious circle of
reasoning, because it is still left up to the evidence to determine how
successful the assumptions are in explaining the phenomena of interest.
Pluralism as the upshot of value-laden inquiry. Because the interests
and values of inquirers vary, and inquirers select background
assumptions in part for their fit with their interests and values,
their background assumptions will also vary. Rather than lamenting this
fact, feminist epistemologists urge us to embrace it (Haraway 1991,
Harding 1998, Longino 2001). A pluralism of theories and research
programs should be accepted as a normal feature of science—as it is,
certainly, in the human sciences. As long as the different research
programs are producing empirical successes not produced by the others,
and avoiding clear error and viciously circular reasoning, there is
good reason to treat the value-biases animating them as epistemic
resources, helping us discover and understand new aspects of the world
and see them in new perspectives, rather than as obstacles to the
search for truth. Feminist science takes its place as one set of
legitimate research programs among others, rather than as something
that replaces the others. The price to be paid for this is the disunity
of science. This does not imply relativism. Value-laden research
programs are still open to internal and external critique. A
naturalized epistemology that rejects neutrality allows that
observations may undermine any background assumptions, including value
judgments.
7. Feminist Critiques and Conceptions of Objectivity
Feminist Critiques of Objectivity. Feminist critiques of objectivity
are directed not against all claims to objectivity, but against
particular conceptions of objectivity. The conceptions of objectivity
considered problematic by feminists include the following: (a)
Subject/object dichotomy: what is really (“objectively”) real exists
independently of knowers. (b) Aperspectivity: “objective” knowledge is
ascertained through “the view from nowhere,” a view that transcends or
abstracts from our particular locations. (c) Detachment: knowers have
an “objective” stance toward what is known when they are emotionally
detached from it. (d) Value-neutrality: knowers have an “objective”
stance toward what is known when they adopt a neutral attitude toward
it, declining to judge it either good or bad. (e) Control: “objective”
knowledge of an object (the way it “really” is) is attained by
controlling it, especially by experimental manipulation, and observing
the regularities it manifests under control. (f) External guidance:
“objective” knowledge consists of representations whose content is
dictated by the way things really are, not by the knower. These ideas
are often combined into a package of claims about science: that its aim
is to know the way things are, independent of knowers, and that
scientists achieve this aim through detachment and control, which
enable them to achieve aperspectivity and external guidance. This
package arose in the 17th-18th centuries, as a philosophical account of
why Newtonian science was superior to its Scholastic predecessor.
According to this account, the predecessor science, which represented
objects as intrinsically possessing secondary qualities and ends,
confused the way things are in themselves with the ways they are
related to emotionally engaged human knowers, who erroneously projected
their own mental states and value judgments onto things. Adoption of
the objective methods listed above enabled the successor scientists to
avoid these errors and achieve an “absolute” conception of the universe
(Williams 1978). Feminists object to each element in this package as a
normative ideal and as a general description of how science works.
Subject/object dichotomy. If the object of science is to grasp things
as they are, independent of knowers, then it is important to draw a
sharp distinction between the knower and the known. Feminists argue
that the assumptions that science or “objective” inquiry aims at, and
achieves, such “absolute” knowledge presupposes a problematic ontology.
When the objects of inquiry are knowers themselves, these assumptions
rule out the possibility that knowers' self-understandings help
constitute the ways knowers are. In other words, it rules out the
possibility that some of our characteristics, such as our gender, are
socially constructed. Ironically, these assumptions may lead people to
make the very projective errors the objectivity package is supposed to
avoid: attributing to the essential natures of the objects of study
what are actually products of people's contingent beliefs and attitudes
about those objects (Haslanger 1995).
Aperspectivity. The ideal of aperspectivity is justified as a means to
achieve knowledge of the way things are, independently of their
relations to knowers. If one views things from no particular position,
without any presuppositions or biases, then the only thing that guides
belief-formation is the object itself (external guidance), not the
knower. Feminists question the intelligibility of a “view from
nowhere,” and a presuppositionless, bias-free science, for both
postmodernist (Haraway 1991) and pragmatist (Antony 1993) reasons.
Representations of the world reflect the interests, positions, and
biases of observers, and could hardly do otherwise, given that
scientific theories always go beyond the evidence offered for them.
Biases are necessary to get theorizing off the ground. Therefore, our
proper project should not be to give up on presuppositions or biases,
but to empirically study which biases are fruitful and which mislead,
and reform scientific practice accordingly, as naturalized epistemology
would recommend (Antony 1993). Some feminist critics argue that the
assumption of aperspectivity is not just an epistemological error. It
generates further errors in scientific theories of the world, which
have pernicious consequences for those occupying subordinate social
positions. In the most radical form of this critique, the practice of
objectivity—assuming that observed regularities reflect the intrinsic
natures of things, and treating those things accordingly—when adopted
by those in power, produces the very regularities taken to vindicate
that assumption. When male observers exercise the power to make women
behave in accordance with their desires (for instance, to elicit female
submission to their aggressive sexual advances), but assume their own
aperspectivity, they misattribute the behavior to women's intrinsic
natures (feminine passivity) rather than to their own socially
positioned power. The androcentric projection of masculine desires onto
women, posing as aperspectival, constitutes an exercise of male power
that causes women to behave in accordance with men's wishes. This
process constitutes the “objectification” of women. It is harmful to
women, because it legitimates the same sexist practices that reinforce
the projection, in a morally vicious circle. And it is epistemically
flawed, in that it misrepresents the modality of observed regularities
(as necessary, rather than socially contingent), as well as their cause
(as generated by the intrinsic nature of the things observed, rather
than by the observer's own stance toward what is observed.) (MacKinnon
1999, Haslanger 1993).
Detachment. The ideal of objectivity as detachment, according to which
good scientists should adopt an emotionally distanced, controlling
stance toward their objects of study, is defended as necessary to avoid
projective error. Keller suggests that it is responsible for the
symbolically “masculine” standing of science that marginalizes women in
science (because women are stereotyped as emotional). Moreover, it
reflects an androcentric perspective, in that it serves mens' neurotic
anxieties about maintaining sharp boundaries between self and other,
and keeping the “feminine” at arms-length (Keller 1985a, Bordo 1987).
Other criticisms of objectivity-as-detachment focus more on the
epistemic defects of emotional distance. A “feeling for the
[individual] organism” may sensitize a scientist to critical data
(Keller 1983).
Value-neutrality. The ideal of objectivity as value-neutrality is
justified as a psychological stance needed to guard against temptations
toward wishful thinking and dogmatic, politically motivated or
ideological reasoning. Feminists argue, on the basis of historical and
sociological investigations of the history and current practice of
science, that this insistence on the value-neutrality of scientists is
self-deceptive and unrealistic (Potter 1993, 2001; Longino 1990, 2001;
Harding 1991, 1998; Wylie 1996). Indeed, it is self-defeating: when
scientists represent themselves as neutral, this blocks their
recognition of the ways their values have shaped their inquiry, and
thereby prevents the exposure of these values to critical scrutiny.
Advocates of neutrality think the only influences of evaluative
presuppositions on science are pernicious. Feminists argue that this
stance ignores the many positive roles value judgments play in guiding
the process and products of inquiry noted above. Other procedures are
available to block the effects of wishful thinking and political
dogmatism on what claims science ultimately accepts, without requiring
scientists to bracket their value judgments (Anderson 1995, Longino
2001).
Control. Experimental contexts, in which scientists elicit regularities
in the behavior of the objects of study by manipulating them under
controlled conditions, are often taken to generate epistemically
privileged evidence about the objects of study. Such evidence is
thought to ground knowledge of how the objects “really are”, in
contrast with evidence about the objects of study generated through
“subjective” modes of interaction with them, such as participant
observation, dialogue, political engagement, and caring for their
needs. Feminists argue that the stance of control is a stance of
social, specifically male, power. The epistemic privilege it enjoys
reflects both androcentrism (a male point of view, misrepresented as
universal) and the social prestige attached to whatever is
gender-symbolized as “masculine” (Merchant 1980, Smith 1974). Such
considerations do not provide legitimate grounds for granting epistemic
privilege to the stance of control. At the same time, they underrate
the epistemic value of experiences gained from loving or cooperative
engagement with the objects of study. The chief feminist complaint
against objectivity-as-control is not that it grounds false theories,
but that the theories it produces generate only a partial view of the
potentialities of the objects of study, reflecting and serving
interests in control over the objects, but not interests in engaging
with the objects in other ways, or in enabling the objects of study, if
they are human, to govern themselves (Tiles 1987).
External guidance. The ideal of external guidance assumes that to
achieve knowledge of the way things “objectively” or “really” are,
independent of knowers, one's beliefs must be guided by the nature of
the object, not by the presuppositions and biases of the knower.
Feminists argue that the contrast between external and internal
(“subjective”) guidance poses a false dichotomy. The underdetermination
of theories by evidence entails that theories cannot be guided purely
by the nature of the object. Inquirers must make numerous, contingent
choices along the way, concerning how to conceive and represent the
object of knowledge, what aspects of it to study, how to interpret
evidence concerning the object, and how to represent the conclusions
drawn (Longino 1990, Nelson 1990). The pretense that sound scientific
theories are the products of purely external guidance obscures the
forces shaping these choices and absolves scientists from
responsibility for defending them. For example, feminists have paid
particular attention to the ways choices of metaphors and narrative
genres constrain scientific explanations (Haraway 1989, 1991). The
decision to narrate the fertilization of egg by sperm as a romance
casts the sperm in an active role, and egg in a passive one, obscuring
the causal role of eggs in bringing about fertilization (Martin 1996).
Similarly, the decision to narrate the transition from ape to hominid
as a heroic drama dictates a focus on presumptively male activities,
such as hunting, as the engine of evolution, obscuring less dramatic
alternatives that are at least equally supported by the data, but that
focus on presumptively female activity (balancing child care needs with
gathering) or on behaviors, such as language use, that are shared by
both males and females (Haraway 1989, Longino 1990).
These feminist criticisms of different conceptions of objectivity share
some common themes. The problematic conceptions of objectivity generate
partial accounts of the world, which they misrepresent as complete and
universal. The forms of partiality they underwrite are either
androcentric (represent the world from a male point of view),
symbolized as “masculine,” or serve male interests (or the interests of
other dominant social positions). They are justified by appealing to
models of cognition that represent error and bias in terms of qualities
that are gender symbolized as “feminine” and stereotypically attributed
to women. Such conceptions of objectivity, because they recommend
avoidance of the “feminine,” function to exclude women from
participation in inquiry or deprive them of epistemic authority. The
problematic conceptions of objectivity ignore the knowledge-enhancing,
epistemically fruitful uses of supposedly “feminine” approaches to
theorizing (e.g., uses of emotional engagement and explicit attention
to perspectival knowledge). By representing partial perspectives as
aperspectival and externally guided, these problematic conceptions of
objectivity induce systematic mistakes on the part of those who embrace
these conceptions. Ironically, the mistakes they induce, such as
projective error (mistaking qualities of the knower or relations of
knower to known for intrinsic qualities of the object known) and
partiality, are the very errors these conceptions of objectivity are
supposed to avoid. Moreover, these conceptions of objectivity tend to
prevent adherents from recognizing and correcting these errors, and so
tend to entrench them in scientific practice.
Feminist Conceptions of Objectivity. The feminist critiques of
objectivity just surveyed identify errors and illegitimate biases in
inquiry, and therefore presuppose their own conceptions of objectivity.
Feminist epistemologists and philosophers of science avoid ontological
accounts (such as subject/object dichotomy), which define objectivity
in terms of an a priori idea of what counts as really real, preferring
to leave open to inquiry what sorts of entity exist. Instead, feminist
conceptions of objectivity are procedural. Products of inquiry are more
objective, the better they are supported by objective procedures. Some
of the more influential feminist conceptions of objectivity include the
following:
Feminist/nonsexist research methods. Rather than offering a
comprehensive account of objectivity, some feminists have offered
methodological guidelines for avoiding the sexist and androcentric
errors and biases that feminists have identified in mainstream science.
Eichler (1988) offers an exemplary work of this kind, explaining how to
avoid androcentrism, overgeneralization, gender insensitivity, and
sexual double standards in research. More ambitiously, feminists have
sought research methods that embody feminist values—for example,
ensuring that gendered features of social phenomena are made salient
(Nielsen 1990, Reinharz 1992). Some theorists argue that feminism
requires controversial methodological standards, such as preferring
qualitative over quantitative methods, or not questioning female
subjects' own interpretations of their experiences (Stanley & Wise
1983). But other feminist researchers vigorously contest such claims
(Greaves, Wylie and Staff, 1995; Jayaratne & Stewart 1991). Harding
(1987b) persuasively argues that there is no single feminist method;
doing science as a feminist requires that one be willing to adopt
various methods, depending on the question under investigation.
Emotional engagement. Various feminist theorists have stressed the
epistemic fruitfulness of emotional engagement with the object of
study. Emotions serve critical epistemic functions in moral and
political inquiry, attuning observers to evaluatively relevant features
of the world (Jaggar 1989, Little 1995). In social scientific inquiry
more generally, emotional engagement with one's subjects of study may
be necessary both to elicit and interpret behaviors of scientific
interest. Ethnographers may need to win the trust of their subjects to
get them to open up, and to achieve a rapport with them to understand
what they are up to. Sympathetic identification with the subjects of
study may generate important criticisms of dominant theories and
significant rival hypotheses (Hrdy 1986). Keller (1985a) has developed
the idea of objectivity as (non-neurotic) emotional engagement in her
ideal of “dynamic objectivity.” Dynamic objectivity utilizes a mode of
perception based on loving attention toward the object. Keller argues
that it is superior to objectivity-as-detachment, in that it does not
express a neurotic need to allay anxieties about maintaining the
independence of the self by dominating the object of study. Longino
(1993b) has objected to Keller's ideal on the ground that, even if it
is true that dynamic objectivity involves a less neurotic mode of
interaction with the world, this does not show that it is epistemically
superior. Keller's case study of Barbara McClintock's pathbreaking
discovery of genetic transposition (1983), represented as an exemplary
manifestation of dynamic objectivity, demonstrates the epistemic
fruitfulness of loving attention to the objects of study without fully
answering Longino's challenge. (It is one thing to demonstrate that a
mode of engagement is epistemically fruitful, another to demonstrate
that it is epistemically superior, across-the-board, to other modes of
engagement).
Reflexivity. Harding (1993) argues that the objectivity of a
representation is greater, the more reflexive is its process of
generation. Reflexivity demands that inquirers place themselves on the
same causal plane as the object of knowledge. They must make explicit
the social positions, interests, background assumptions, biases, and
other contingent, perspectival features of themselves that shaped the
questions, methods, interpretations, and modes of presentation of the
claims the knower accepts as knowledge. Reflexivity affirms the
partiality of representations without denying their possible claim to
truth. A representation can be true without being the whole truth about
the object represented. It enhances objectivity by avoiding a
narcissistic confusion of one's own partial perspective with a
comprehensive view, and by highlighting contingencies of representation
that could be questioned. Harding argues that inclusion of marginalized
groups into inquiry will improve reflexivity, because the marginalized
are more likely to notice and take issue with features of accepted
representations that are due to the unquestioned adoption of the
perspectives of the dominant. Democratic inclusion is therefore an
implication of reflexivity. Harding's ideal of “strong objectivity”
includes both reflexivity and democratic inclusion as the key features
of more objective processes of inquiry. She casts this ideal as a
reconfiguration of standpoint theory, because it accords the
standpoints of marginalized groups an indispensable role in producing
objective knowledge. However, strong objectivity does not accord
epistemic privilege to the standpoints of the oppressed, considered by
themselves. Rather, it prefers representation produced by communities
that include them over representations produced by communities that
exclude them.
Democratic discussion. Longino (1990, 2001) has developed most fully a
conception of objectivity based on democratic discussion. Her key idea
is that the production of knowledge is a social enterprise, secured
through the critical and cooperative interactions of inquirers. The
products of this social enterprise are more objective, the more
responsive they are to criticism from all points of view. This idea
builds on a long tradition including J.S. Mill, Karl Popper, and Paul
Feyerabend (Lloyd 1997a). Feminists develop this tradition by offering
(i) a more articulate conception of “all points of view,” stressing the
influence of the social positions of inquirers on the representations
they produce; (ii) a more empirically informed account of the social
interactions characteristic of different communities of inquiry (e.g.,
Potter 1993, 2001); (iii) a greater stress on the importance of
equality among inquirers. In Longino's influential account, a community
of inquirers is objective—entitled to credit its products as
knowledge—if it: (1) offers public venues for the criticism of
knowledge claims; (2) responds to criticisms by changing its theories
according to (3) publicly recognized standards of evaluation; and (4)
follows a norm of equality of intellectual authority among its members.
The requirement of equality of intellectual authority secures the
democratic credentials of the theory. It is also its most criticized
element, given the need to recognize differences in expertise and
competence among inquirers. Advocates of the democratic discussion
model of objectivity have responded by refining the norm of equality so
as to distinguish legitimate differences of expertise and competence
from illegitimate exercises of social power to exclude some criticisms,
such as those emerging from disadvantaged social positions, from a
serious hearing (Anderson 1995c, Longino 2001).
Pluralist Themes in Feminist Conceptions of Objectivity. The
conceptions of objectivity criticized by feminists identify objectivity
with a single point of view, the “view from nowhere,” and dismiss all
other points of view as false or biased. Most feminist conceptions of
objectivity accommodate both methodological and theoretical pluralism.
Different communities of inquiry take an interest in different aspects
of the world, and develop various partial theories to satisfy varied
epistemic and pragmatic values. While no empirical theory can be
justified unless it is supported by evidence, the underdetermination of
theories by evidence permits the development of a plurality of
theories, each of which may claim its own successes. Most feminists
resist the thought that these varied theories, to the extent that they
contain truths, must eventually be unified into a single grand theory
of everything, based on a single observation language and a single set
of theoretical terms. As long as different communities of inquiry and
their associated theories are producing empirical successes in
accordance with publicly recognized standards, while holding themselves
accountable to criticism from all sides, their products may each count
as objective, however irreducibly plural the content of their theories
may be (Longino 2001, Harding 1991, 1998).
8. Epistemic Authority
Recent work in naturalized epistemology has stressed our pervasive
epistemic interdependence, especially due to our unavoidable reliance
on testimony (Nelson 1990). Because inquiry is collaborative, what we
believe is partially determined by who we believe. Decisions about who
to believe depend in turn on attributions of epistemic authority, which
depend on judgments of people's competence, expertise, reliability, and
trustworthiness. Feminist epistemologists explore the ways gender and
other hierarchical social relations influence attributions of epistemic
authority, considering their impact on (1) general models of knowledge;
(2) the epistemic standing of knowers; and (3) whose claims various
epistemic communities accept, and ought to accept, as credible.
General Models of Knowledge. At the most abstract level, gendered ideas
about epistemic authority can distort our general models of knowledge.
Code (1991) argues that contemporary analytic epistemology's core model
of propositional knowledge implicitly presupposes a male knower. The
instances of knowledge analytic epistemology takes to be paradigmatic
when it analyses the formula “S knows that P” are propositions about
readily observable mind-independent objects. To take these as the
paradigmatic instances of knowledge invites a model of the knower as
emotionally detached, impersonally oriented to things rather than
persons, and oriented in an “objective” posture toward the object of
knowledge. These features of knowers are symbolically gendered
masculine and stereotypically attributed to men. This fact, in
conjunction with the cultural representation of masculinity and
femininity as opposed and mutually exclusive, implicitly denies
epistemic authority to women. While Code pays attention to this
injustice, her main focus is on the ways gender symbolism and gender
stereotypes distort epistemology's model of knowledge. She argues that
knowledge of other persons rather than of propositions should be taken
as a primary model of knowledge. Such second-personal knowledge calls
the implicit masculinity of knowers into question, since getting to
know others typically requires intimacy, dialogue, empathy and other
characteristics that are gender symbolized as “feminine.”
While Code's proposal to replace propositional knowledge with personal
knowledge as the core model of knowledge has not been generally
followed, recent epistemology's focus on the indispensability of
testimony to inquiry has enabled feminist epistemologists to take
Code's ideas in a different direction, by investigating the dependence
of propositional knowledge on knowledge of persons. In contexts where
unimpeded communication against a background of overwhelming consensus
is taken for granted, this fact is obscured. It is explicit in
anthropology, where inquirers must face not just language barriers but
an alien world that they initially lack the conceptual resources to
interpret. Anthropologists are keenly aware that they must cultivate
personal relationships with native informants to gain access to the
natives' situated knowledge of their cultures. This requires reflection
on the ways differences in power, interest, personality, and social
situation between the anthropologist and his or her informants
influence the testimony elicited in personal interaction and its
interpretation. Feminist epistemology has investigated reflexive
sociology to call into question models of testimony as a transparent
and unidirectional transmission of objective information, highlighting
instead testimony's dialogic, strategic, and empathetic features, as
well as the importance and difficulty of cultivating epistemically
fruitful relations of mutual trust across differences in power (Bergin
2002; Lugones 1987).
Epistemic Standing of Knowers. Other feminist epistemologists focus on
the impact of gender and other hierarchical social relations on the
epistemic authority of knowers. Dominant groups tend to accord
epistemic authority to themselves and withhold it from subordinates.
They promote, as external markers or assurances of epistemic
competence, trustworthiness, and hence authority, characteristics they
have, or are stereotypically supposed to have (such as a gentleman's
sense of honor), that subordinates lack or are stereotypically supposed
to lack (Addelson 1983; Shapin 1994). Such power-distorted practices of
assigning epistemic authority commit an epistemic injustice against
members of subordinate groups, undermining their ability to participate
in collaborative inquiry (Fricker 1998, 2003). Fricker (2007)
distinguishes two types of epistemic injustice commonly committed
against the disadvantaged: testimonial injustice and hermeneutical
injustice. Testimonial injustice occurs when people discount the
credibility what others say on account of prejudice against their
social group. Hermeneutical injustice occurs when people fail to
respond adequately to others' experiences and complaints in virtue of
using an interpretive framework that distorts their testimony or
renders it unintelligible. For example, widespread acceptance of a “coy
female” model of dating as a kind of feminine play-acting prevents
people from interpreting a woman's “no” as really meaning “no” in the
context of date rape.
Feminist epistemologists offer various responses to the problem of
power-distorted assignments of epistemic authority. Bar On (1993)
argues that claims to speak and be given a serious hearing need to be
detached from claims to epistemic authority. While agreeing with Bar On
that the original claim of feminist standpoint theory to some kind of
epistemic privilege must be abandoned, Janack (1997) and Fricker (1999)
argue that we cannot avoid judgments of epistemic authority; hence our
task must be to reconfigure the norms for ascribing epistemic authority
more justly.
Whose Claims Epistemic Communities Should Accept. Should the case for
changing norms of epistemic authority be made simply on grounds of
justice to inquirers, or can an epistemic case be made for it as well?
Bar On (1993) and Janack (1997) suggest that the case for epistemic
inclusion is moral rather than epistemic. Code (2004), among many
others, argues that besides committing an epistemic injustice against
members of subordinate groups, power-distorted allocations of epistemic
authority lead to biased and partial theories that tend to reinforce
social inequality. Harding (1993) and Longino (1990, 2001) agree that
more inclusive and egalitarian communities of inquiry are not just
morally but also epistemically superior, in that they are able to
produce less biased, more objective theories. The general case for such
a view relies on the phenomenon of situated knowledge. The premise of
situated knowledge entails that information is asymmetrically
distributed across social positions. Any moderately complex inquiry
will need to be undertaken by a community of inquirers who draw from
these dispersed sources of knowledge, pooling information and making it
available to the community as a whole. This process requires that those
with relevant situated knowledge be recognized as having epistemic
authority to testify about it. Situated knowledge is unavailable, or
imperfectly available, to the community insofar as it allocates
epistemic authority to individuals in ways not warranted by their
underlying epistemic competence and trustworthiness, or in ways that
prevent people in certain social positions from improving their
epistemic competence and establishing relations of trust with others.
The theories that result from such distorted allocations of epistemic
authority will tend to be partial and biased.
Many feminist epistemologists advocate democratic, egalitarian norms
for allocating epistemic authority as a way to overcome epistemic
injustice and produce more objective theories (Anderson 1995c; Longino
1990, 2001; Potter 1996) This raises the question of what a democratic
allocation of epistemic authority would look like. Should norms for
ascribing epistemic authority treat group identity as irrelevant, so
that, other epistemically relevant features being held equal,
individuals of different genders, races, castes, etc. should be granted
equal epistemic authority? Or might an inquirer's social identity be
relevant to the epistemic authority she can legitimately claim?
Longino's (1990, 2001) norm of “tempered” equality of intellectual
authority could be read to suggest a group-blind norm for allocating
epistemic authority. Other feminist epistemologists, sometimes
influenced by standpoint theory, argue that group identity can
contingently confer an epistemic advantage with respect to answering
certain questions, or getting access to certain critical evidence
relevant to answering them. Hence, allocations of epistemic authority
may sometimes be sensitive to group membership, depending on the
context and question being asked (Alcoff 2001; Anderson 1995c; Wylie
2003). This does not necessarily entail holding that A has more
epistemic authority than B with respect to question Q in virtue of A's
social identity. It may simply entail that a community of inquirers
that includes members with A's social identity has more epistemic
authority than one that lacks such members.
Other feminist epistemologists suggest additional remedies for
power-distorted biases in allocating epistemic authority. Fricker
(2003) proposes cultivating the virtue of “reflexive critical
openness”: striving for awareness of one's prejudicial biases in
ascribing epistemic authority, and correcting one's credibility
judgments to counteract those biases. Jones (2002), in a similar
spirit, proposes specific rules for checking such biases when
confronted with testimony one finds astonishing. These include
undertaking independent assessments of the credibility of the witness
and the plausibility of what they say; and letting the presumption
against accepting some astonishing testimony be rebutted when one has
good reason to distrust one's distrust of the witness. Janack (1997)
argues that we should only trust those inquirers who are willing to be
held accountable for their constructions of knowledge claims, rather
than hiding behind the pretense of value-neutrality. Further proposals
along these lines await continued research on the causes of and
corrections for bias in allocating epistemic authority.
9. Trends in Feminist Epistemology
When Harding (1986) proposed her classification of feminist
epistemologies into empiricism, standpoint theory, and postmodernism,
she cast them as offering three fundamentally contrasting frameworks.
Empiricism was thought to presuppose an unsituated, politically neutral
subject of knowledge, whereas standpoint theory and postmodernism
offered different approaches to the problem of situated knowledge—the
first upholding an epistemic privilege of one situation over others,
the other embracing a relativism of standpoints. Trends in feminist
epistemology in the last fifteen years have blurred the distinctions
among feminist empiricism, standpoint theory, and feminist
postmodernism—trends Harding herself both predicted and advanced (1990,
1991, 1998). Most importantly, all three approaches to feminist
epistemology embrace pluralism and reject totalizing theories. All
three approaches also reject the traditional epistemological project of
validating epistemic norms from a transcendent viewpoint, because they
deny that there is any such viewpoint to be had.
Feminist standpoint theory. The postmodernist critique of standpoint
theory, in conjunction with the proliferation of subaltern women's
standpoints (black, Latina, lesbian, postcolonial, etc.) has led most
standpoint theorists to abandon the search for a single feminist
standpoint that can claim overarching epistemic superiority. Feminist
standpoint theorists have therefore moved in a pluralistic direction,
acknowledging a multiplicity of epistemically informative situated
standpoints (Harding 1991, 1998; Collins 1990). They claim that there
are important things to learn from taking seriously the perspectives of
all marginalized groups—not just of various groups of women, but men
and women in postcolonial societies, men and women of color, gay men,
and so forth. A system of knowledge that draws on their insights and
starts from their predicaments will be richer than one that draws only
on the insights and starts from the predicaments of privileged groups
alone (Harding 1993, 1998). This shifts the privilege claimed on behalf
of subaltern standpoints from the context of justification to the
context of discovery: thinking from subaltern standpoints is more
fruitful than confining one's thinking to dominant perspectives. And
the fruitfulness in question is judged more often on pragmatic
grounds—thinking from these standpoints enables us to envision and
realize more just social relations (Hartsock 1996). Shifting from
claims of epistemic privilege in access to truth to claims of practical
advantage in discovering morally or politically significant truths has
been a key strategy defenders of standpoint theory (Collins 1996;
Harding 1996; Hartsock 1996) have used against postmodernist critics
such as Hekman (1996). Many standpoint theorists have also turned to
focusing more sharply on the epistemic value of the experiences of
subordinated people, as opposed to making categorical claims about
group differences in cognitive style. In her important discussion of
recent debates in feminist standpoint theory, Wylie (2003) confirms
that a consensus has emerged among feminist epistemologists on two
points: (1) a rejection of “essentialism” (the idea that the social
groups defining any standpoint have a necessary and fixed nature, or
that their members do or ought to think alike) and (2) a rejection of
attempts to grant “automatic epistemic privilege” to any particular
standpoint. Instead, Wylie stresses how the social situation of
“insider-outsiders” (members of disadvantaged groups who need accurate
knowledge of the worlds of the privileged in order to navigate them
successfully) can sometimes afford a contingent epistemic privilege or
advantage in solving particular problems. Thus, standpoint theorists'
focus on pluralism reflects a productive interaction with feminist
postmodernism; their shift toward pragmatism, experience, and
contingent epistemic advantages of the disadvantaged reflects a
productive interaction with feminist empiricism.
Feminist postmodernism. Wariness of the fractionating and centrifugal
forces in postmodernism has led some feminists sympathetic to
postmodernism to seek middle, more stable grounds that feminist
empiricists, standpoint theorists, and postmodernists can share.
Haraway (1989) stands out among feminist postmodernists for the
tributes she pays to the achievements of feminist scientists working
within empiricist standards of evaluation. She also seeks to
reconstruct ideas of objectivity and epistemic responsibility
consistent with situated knowledge (1991). Fraser (1995) and Fraser
& Nicholson (1990) also urge a reformulation of the lessons of
postmodernism, toward pragmatism, fallibilism, and contextualization of
knowledge claims—all features fully compatible with naturalized
feminist empiricism—as against categorical rejections of large-scale
social theory, history, normative philosophy, and even humanist values.
While it remains to be seen whether feminist postmodernists will
actually take up these calls, they signal directions in which
postmodernism could be taken.
Feminist empiricism. While early, nonphilosophical feminist science
criticism by working scientists may have presupposed a naive version of
empiricism, attempts by feminist epistemologists to make sense of
feminist science criticism have, following Quine, incorporated
explicitly pragmatist and naturalizing themes into feminist empiricism.
Thus, feminist empiricists today stress the centrality of situated
knowledge, the interplay of facts and values, the absence of
transcendental standpoints, and the plurality of theories. These themes
converge with those of postmodernism.
Remaining differences. The differences that remain among feminist
postmodernists, empiricists, and standpoint theorists partially reflect
different choices of tools. Feminist postmodernists use the tools of
poststructuralism and literary theory. Feminist empiricists prefer the
tools of analytic philosophy of science. Some versions of standpoint
theory, such as Collins' (1990), rest on an identity politics alien to
both postmodernists and empiricists. (To the extent that standpoint
theory remains tied to a materialist epistemology, as in Hartsock
(1996) and MacKinnon (1999), it is fully compatible with feminist
empiricist naturalized epistemology.)
Other differences reflect different attitudes toward and conceptions of
objectivity. Although feminist postmodernism has relativist tendencies,
its skepticism and stress on instability undermines both the
purportedly all-encompassing stance of objectivity and the
self-contained, complacent parochiality of relativism. What's missing
is not the thought that critique is possible, but any form of critique
that enables one to build and synthesize rather than tear down and
deconstruct claims to know. Although Haraway reconceives objectivity in
terms of epistemic responsibility, it is hard to hold knowers
accountable for their claims if they never stick to any claims for very
long (Bordo 1990). Harding (1993, 1998) continues standpoint theory's
project of trying to identify an epistemically superior approach that
can claim “strong objectivity.” Feminist empiricism offers an
alternative procedural account of objectivity (Longino 2001). Both
envision critical theory as a constructive, not just a deconstructive
project. But standpoint theory remains residually attached to claims of
epistemic superiority for feminist science, whereas feminist empiricism
is concerned rather simply to make room at the pluralist table for
feminist approaches to science, without asserting epistemic superiority
on their behalf.
10. External Criticisms of Feminist Epistemology
Outside critics of feminist epistemology have argued that the entire
research program is flawed at its foundations. Leading critiques of
feminist epistemology include a collection of essays in the Monist,
77(4) (1994), Gross and Levitt (1994), Haack (1993), and Pinnick,
Koertge and Almeder (2003). The most important criticism of feminist
epistemology, found in all these works, is that it corrupts the search
for truth by conflating facts with values and imposing political
constraints on the conclusions it will accept. Truths inconvenient to a
feminist perspective will be censored, and false views promoted because
they support the feminist cause. In a closely allied charge, also found
in these works, critics accuse feminist epistemologists of a corrosive
cynicism about science, claiming that they reject it wholesale as a raw
imposition of patriarchal and imperialist power. Feminist
epistemologists are said to hold that there are no objective standards
of truth and that beliefs are governed by the struggle for political
power. On this account, feminists are seen as holding that, since
everyone else is engaged in a cynical power-play, they may as well join
the battle and try to impose their beliefs on everyone else.
Defenders of feminist epistemology reply that these criticisms depend
on serious misreadings of the feminist research program. They argue
that feminists do not reject objectivity and science, but rather seek
to improve it by correcting sexist and androcentric biases in
scientific inquiry, and by promoting criticism of research from all
points of view (Lloyd 1995a, 1995b, 1997a, 1997b, Nelson 1990). Nor do
they deny that science as currently constituted discovers genuine
truths. The complaint is rather that, as dominantly practiced, it
offers a partial view of the world that is primarily oriented to
discovering those truths that serve particular human interests in
material control and maintaining current social hierarchies (Harding
1986, 1998, 1993; Tiles 1987). Feminist epistemologists observe that
the democratic and egalitarian norms for cognitive authority they
accept, along with their requirement that the scientific community be
open and responsive to criticism from all quarters, are incompatible
with censorship of evidence, argument, or conclusions on political
grounds, and with ignoring or suppressing evidence that undermines any
theory, including theories inspired by feminist values (Longino 1990,
1993a, 2001; Anderson 2004—see Other Internet Resources). Although
facts and values are intertwined, they play fundamentally different
roles in shaping sound scientific inquiry, such that attention to
values does not displace or compete with regard for the evidence
(Anderson 1995b).
A second major charge outside critics make against feminist
epistemology is that it accepts traditional stereotypes about women's
thinking (as intuitive, holistic, emotional, etc.) and uncritically
valorizes these stereotypes. This leads to several problems. There is
no evidence that women all do think alike or that thinking in a
“feminine” way reliably leads to truth. Acceptance of conventional
stereotypes about women also puts unjust pressure on women who think
otherwise to conform to feminine cognitive styles. (Haack 1993).
Valorization of “feminine” ways of thinking may also trap women in
traditional gender roles and help justify patriarchy (Nanda 2003).
Promotion of feminist epistemology may carve out a limited “separate
sphere” for female inquirers, but one that will turn into an
intellectual ghetto, much as female scholars in an earlier era were
largely confined to “feminine” fields such as home economics and
nursing (Baber 1994).
Defenders of feminist epistemology reply that the critics are attacking
an obsolete version of feminist epistemology that was only briefly—and
even at the time, controversially—entertained when the field was
launched in the 1980s (Wylie 2003, Anderson 2004—see Other Internet
Resources). It has since been superceded, for many of the reasons the
critics have articulated, plus others arising from the critiques of
black and Latina feminists and feminist postmodernists.
Further development of external critiques of feminist epistemology
awaits the critics' engagement with the feminist epistemology's
defenders and with current developments in the field.
Bibliography
* Addelson, Kathryn, 1983, “The Man of Professional
Wisdom”, in Harding and Hintikka 1983.
* Alcoff, Linda, 2001, “On Judging Epistemic
Credibility: Is Social Identity Relevant?”, in Engendering
Rationalities, N. Tuana and S. Morgan, (eds.), Albany: SUNY Press.
* Alcoff, Linda, and Elizabeth Potter, (eds.) 1993,
Feminist Epistemologies, New York: Routledge.
* Altmann, Jeanne, 1974, “Observational study of
behavior: Sampling methods”, Behavior, 49: 227-267
* Anderson, Elizabeth, 1995a, “Feminist
Epistemology: An Interpretation and Defense”, Hypatia, 10: 50-84.
* –––, 1995b, “Knowledge, Human Interests, and
Objectivity in Feminist Epistemology”, Philosophical Topics, 23: 27-58.
* –––, 1995c, “The Democratic University: the Role
of Justice in the Production of Knowledge”, Social Philosophy and
Policy, 12: 186-219.
* Antony, Louise, 1993, “Quine as Feminist: The
Radical Import of Naturalized Epistemology”, in Antony and Witt 1993.
* Antony, Louise, and Charlotte Witt, (eds.), 1993
[2002], A Mind of One's Own, Boulder: Westview Press, 1993; 2nd
edition, 2002.
* Baber, Harriet, 1994, “The Market for Feminist
Epistemology”, Monist, 77 (4): 403-423.
* Bar On, Bat-Ami, 1993. “Marginality and Epistemic
Privilege”, in Alcoff and Potter 1993.
* Belenky, Mary Field, et al, 1986, Women's Ways of
Knowing, New York: Basic Books.
* Bell, Diane, Patricia Caplan, and Karim
Wazir-Jahan Begum, 1993, Gendered Fields : Women, Men, and Ethnography,
London/New York: Routledge.
* Bem, Sandra, 1993, The Lenses of Gender, New
Haven: Yale University Press.
* Benhabib, Seyla, 1995, “Feminism and
Postmodernism”, in Benhabib, et al. 1995.
* Benhabib, Seyla, Judith Butler, Drucilla Cornell
and Nancy Fraser, 1995, Feminist Contentions, New York: Routledge.
* Bergin, Lisa, 2002, “Testimony, epistemic
difference, and privilege: how feminist epistemology can improve our
understanding of the communication of knowledge”, Social Epistemology,
16: 197-213.
* Bleier, Ruth, 1984, Science and Gender: A Critique
of Biology and its Theories on Women, New York: Pergamon.
* Bordo, Susan, 1987, The Flight to Objectivity:
Essays on Cartesianism and Culture, Albany: State University of New
York Press.
* –––, 1990, “Feminism, Postmodernism, and Gender
Skepticism”, In Nicholson.
* Butler, Judith, 1990, Gender Trouble, New York:
Routledge.
* –––, 1993, Bodies that Matter, New York: Routledge.
* Campbell, Richmond, 1998, Illusions of Paradox,
Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield.
* Clayton, Susan and Faye Crosby, 1992, Justice,
Gender, and Affirmative Action, Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
* Code, Lorraine, 1991, What Can She Know?, Ithaca,
New York: Cornell University Press.
* –––, 2004, “The Power of Ignorance”, Philosophical
Papers, 33: 291-308.
* Collins, Patricia Hill, 1990, Black Feminist
Thought, Boston: Unwin Hyman.
* –––, 1996, “Comment on Hekman's ‘Truth and
Method’: Where's the Power?”, Signs, 22: 375-381.
* Crenshaw, Kimberlé, 1989, “Demarginalizing
the Intersection of Race and Sex”, University of Chicago Legal Forum,
pp. 139-167; reprinted in D. Kairys (ed.), The Politics of Law: A
Progressive Critique, 2nd edition, New York: Pantheon, 1990, 195-217.
* Diamond, Cora, 1991, “Knowing Tornadoes and Other
Things”, New Literary History, 22: 1001-15.
* Duran, Jane, 1991, Toward a Feminist Epistemology,
Savage, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield.
* Eichler, Margrit, 1988, Nonsexist Research
Methods: A Practical Guide, Winchester, Mass.: Allen & Unwin.
* Fausto-Sterling, 1985, Myths of Gender, New York:
Basic Books.
* Flax, Jane, 1983, “Political Philosophy and the
Patriarchal Unconscious”, in Harding and Hintikka 1983.
* Fraser, Nancy, 1995, “False Antitheses”, in
Benhabib et al., 1995.
* Fraser, Nancy and Linda Nicholson, 1990, “Social
Criticism without Philosophy”, in Nicholson 1990.
* Fricker, Miranda, 1998, “Rational Authority and
Social Power: Towards a Truly Social Epistemology”, Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society, 98 (2): 159-177.
* –––, 1999, “Epistemic Oppression and Epistemic
Privilege”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy (Supplementary Volume), 25:
191-210.
* –––, 2003, “Epistemic Injustice and a Role for
Virtue in the Politics of Knowing”, Metaphilosophy, 34: 154-173.
* –––, 2007, Epistemic Injustice, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
* Garry, Ann, and Marilyn Pearsall (eds.) 1989,
Women, Knowledge, and Reality, Boston: Unwin Hyman.
* Gilligan, Carol, 1982, In a Different Voice,
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
* Greaves, Lorraine, Wylie, Alison and the Staff of
the Battered Women's Advocacy Center, 1995, “Women and Violence:
Feminist Practice and Quantitative Method”, in Changing Methods, Sandra
Burt and Lorraine Code, (eds.), Peterborough, Ontario: Broadview Press.
* Gross, Paul and Levitt, Norman, 1994, Higher
Superstition: The Academic Left and its Quarrels with Science,
Baltimore: Johns Hopkins.
* Haack, Susan, 1993, “Epistemological Reflections
of an Old Feminist”, Reason Papers, 18: 31-42. Reprinted as “Knowledge
and Propaganda” in Pinnick, Koertge and Almeder, 2003.
* Haraway, Donna, 1989, Primate Visions, New York:
Routledge.
* –––, 1991, “Situated Knowledges”, In Simians,
Cyborgs, and Women, New York: Routledge.
* Harding, Sandra, 1986, The Science Question in
Feminism, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
* –––, (ed.), 1987a, Feminism and Methodology:
Social Science Issues, Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
* –––, 1987b, “Is There a Feminist Method?”, in
Harding 1987a.
* –––, 1990, “Feminism, Science, and the
Anti-Enlightenment Critiques”, in Nicholson 1990.
* –––, 1991, Whose science? Whose knowledge?,
Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
* –––, 1993, “Rethinking Standpoint Epistemology:
‘What is Strong Objectivity?’”, in Alcoff and Potter 1993.
* –––, (ed.), 1993, The “Racial” Economy of Science,
Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
* –––, 1996, “Comment on Hekman's ‘Truth and
Method’: Whose standpoint needs the regimes of Truth and Reality?”,
Signs, 22: 382-391.
* –––, 1998, Is Science Multicultural?:
Postcolonialisms, Feminisms, and Epistemologies, Bloomington, Ind.:
Indiana University Press.
* –––, and Merrill Hintikka, (eds.), 1983,
Discovering Reality, Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel; Boston: Kluwer.
* –––, and Jean O'Barr, (eds.), 1987, Sex and
Scientific Inquiry, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
* Hare-Mustin, Rachel and Jeanne Maracek, 1994,
“Gender and the Meaning of Difference: Postmodernism and Psychology”,
In Theorizing Feminism, Anne Herrmann and Abigail Stewart, (eds.),
Boulder, Col.: Westview.
* Hartsock, Nancy, 1987, “The Feminist Standpoint:
Developing the Ground for a Specifically Feminist Historical
Materialism”, In Harding 1987a.
* –––, 1996, “Comment on Hekman's ‘Truth and
Method’: Truth or Justice”, Signs, 22: 367-73.
* Haslanger, Sally, 1993, “On Being Objective and
Being Objectified”, in Antony and Witt 1993.
* –––, 1995, “Ontology and Social Construction”,
Philosophical Topics, 23: 95-125.
* –––, 2000, “Gender and Race: (What) Are They?
(What) Do We Want Them To Be?”, Noûs, 34 (1): 31–55.
* Hays-Gilpin, Kelley; Whitley, David, (eds.), 1998,
Reader in Gender Archaeology, New York: Routledge.
* Hekman, Susan, 1996, “Truth and Method: Feminist
Standpoint Theory Revisited”, Signs, 22: 341-365.
* Hrdy, Sarah, 1981, The Woman that Never Evolved,
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
* –––, 1986, “Empathy, Polyandry, and the Myth of
the Coy Female”, In Feminist Approaches to Science, Ruth Bleier, (ed.),
New York: Pergamon.
* Hubbard, Ruth, 1990, The Politics of Women's
Biology, New Brunswick, N.J.: Rutgers University Press.
* Hundleby, Catherine, 1997, “Where Standpoint
Stands Now”, Women and Politics, 18: 25-43.
* Hull, Gloria, Patricia Scott, and Barbara Smith,
(eds.), 1982, All the Women Are White, All the Blacks Are Men, But Some
of Us Are Brave, Old Westbury, N.Y.: Feminist Press.
* Jaggar, Alison, 1989, “Love and Knowledge: Emotion
in Feminist Epistemology”, in Garry and Pearsall 1989.
* Janack, Marianne, 1997, “Standpoint Epistemology
Without the ‘Standpoint’? An Examination of Epistemic Privilege and
Epistemic Authority”, Hypatia, 12: 125-139.
* Jayaratne, Toby and Abigail Stewart, 1991,
“Quantitative and Qualitative Methods in the Social Sciences: Current
Feminist Issues and Practical Strategies”, in Beyond Methodology, Mary
Fonow and Judith Cook, (eds.), Bloomington, Ind.: University of Indiana
Press.
* Jones, Karen, 2002, “The Politics of Credibility”,
in Antony and Witt 2002, 2nd edition.
* Kahneman, Daniel, Paul Slovic and Amos Tversky,
1982, Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
* Keller, Evelyn Fox, 1983, A Feeling for the
Organism, San Francisco: W.H. Freeman.
* –––, 1985a, Reflections on Gender and Science, New
Haven: Yale University Press.
* –––, 1985b, “The Force of the Pacemaker Concept in
Theories of Aggregation in Cellular Slime Mold”, in Keller 1985a.
* –––, 1992, Secrets of Life, Secrets of Death:
Essays on Language, Gender, and Science, New York: Routledge.
* Kalbfleisch, Pamela, (ed.), 1995, Gender, Power,
and Communication in Human Relationships, Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum.
* Kuhn, Thomas, 1977, “Objectivity, Value Judgment
and Theory Choice”, In The Essential Tension, Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
* Lacey, Hugh, 1999, Is Science Value Free?, New
York: Routledge.
* Leacock, Eleanor Burke, 1981, Myths of Male
Dominance, New York: Monthly Review Press.
* Little, Margaret, 1995, “Seeing and Caring: the
Role of Affect in Feminist Moral Epistemology”, Hypatia, 10: 117-137.
* Lloyd, Elisabeth, 1993, “Pre-Theoretical
Assumptions in Evolutionary Explanations of Female Sexuality”,
Philosophical Studies, 69: 139-153.
* –––, 1995a, “Feminism as Method: What Scientists
Get that Philosophers Don't”, Philosophical Topics, 23: 189-220.
* –––, 1995b, “Objectivity and the Double Standard
for Feminist Epistemologies”, Synthese, 104: 351-381.
* –––, 1997a, “Feyerabend, Mill, and Pluralism”,
Philosophy of Science, 64: 396-407.
* –––, 1997b, “Science and Anti-Science: Objectivity
and its Real Enemies”, in Nelson, Lynn and Jack Nelson, (eds.),
Feminism, Science, and the Philosophy of Science, Dordrecht: Kluwer,
217-259.
* Longino, Helen, and Doell, Ruth, 1983, “Body,
Bias, and Behavior”, Signs, 9: 206-227.
* Longino, Helen, 1989, “Can there Be a Feminist
Science?”, in Garry and Pearsall 1989.
* –––, 1990, Science as Social Knowledge, Princeton,
N.J.: Princeton University Press.
* –––, 1993a, “Essential Tensions—Phase Two:
Feminist, Philosophical, and Social Studies of Science”, in Antony and
Witt 1993.
* –––, 1993b, “Subjects, Power, and Knowledge:
Description and Prescription in Feminist Philosophy of Science”, in
Alcoff and Potter 1993.
* –––, 1994, “In Search of Feminist Epistemology”,
Monist, 77: 472-485.
* –––, 2001, The Fate of Knowledge, Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
* Lorde, Audre, 1984, Sister Outsider, Trumansburg,
NY: Crossing Press.
* Lugones, Maria, 1987, “Playfulness,
‘World’-Traveling, and Loving Perception”, Hypatia, 2: 3-19.
* Lugones, Maria, and Elizabeth Spelman, 1983, “Have
We Got a Theory for You! Feminist Theory, Cultural Imperialism, and the
Demand for ‘The Woman's Voice’?”, Women's Studies International Forum,
6: 573-581.
* Lukács, Georg, 1971, “Reification and the
Consciousness of the Proletariat”, in History and Class Consciousness,
Rodney Livingstone (trans.), Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press
* MacKinnon, Catherine, 1999, Toward a Feminist
Theory of the State, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
* Martin, Emily, 1996, “The Egg and the Sperm: How
Science has Constructed a Romance Based on Stereotypical Male-Female
Roles”, in Feminism and Science, Evelyn Fox-Keller and Helen Longino,
(eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
* Marx, Karl, 1964, The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis
Bonaparte, New York: International Publishers.
* Merchant, Carolyn, 1980, The Death of Nature:
Women, Ecology, and the Scientific Revolution, New York: Harper and Row.
* Moulton, Janice, 1983, “A Paradigm of Philosophy:
The Adversary Method”, in Harding and Hintikka 1983.
* Nanda, Meera, 2003, “Modern Science as the
Standpoint of the Oppressed: Dewey Meets the Buddha of India's Dalits”,
in Pinnick, Koertge and Almeder.
* Nelson, Lynn Hankinson, 1990, Who Knows: From
Quine to a Feminist Empiricism, Philadelphia, Pa.: Temple University
Press.
* –––, 1993, “Epistemological Communities”, in
Alcoff and Potter 1993.
* Nicholson, Linda, (ed.), 1990,
Feminism/Postmodernism, New York and London: Routledge.
* Nielsen, Joyce, (ed.), 1990, Feminist Research
Methods, Boulder, Col.: Westview.
* Okin, Susan, 1989, Justice, Gender and the Family,
New York: Basic Books.
* Pinnick, Cassandra, Noretta Koertge and Robert
Almeder, (eds.), 2003, Scrutinizing Feminist Epistemology: An
Examination of Gender in Science, New Brunswick: Rutgers.
* Potter, Elizabeth, 1993, “Gender and Epistemic
Negotiation”, in Alcoff and Potter 1993.
* –––, 1996, “Loopholes, Gaps, and What is Held
Fast: Democratic Epistemology and Claims to Recovered Memories”,
Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology, 3: 238-254.
* –––, 2001, Gender and Boyle's Law of Gases,
Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
* Putnam, Hilary, 1981, Reason, Truth, and History,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
* Quine, W. V. O., 1963, “Two Dogmas of Empiricism.”
in From a Logical Point of View, New York: Harper & Row.
* –––, 1969, “Epistemology Naturalized”, in
Ontological Relativity and Other Essays, New York: Columbia University
Press.
* Reinharz, Shulamit, 1992, Feminist Methods in
Social Research, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
* Rooney, Phyllis, 1991, “Gendered Reason: Sex
Metaphor and Conceptions of Reason”, Hypatia, 6: 77-103.
* Rose, Hilary, 1987, “Hand, Brain, and Heart: A
Feminist Epistemology for the Natural Sciences”, in Harding and O'Barr
1987.
* Rose, Suzanna, 1989, “Women Biologists and the
‘Old Boy’ Network”, Women's Studies International Forum, 12: 349-54.
* Schiebinger, Londa, 1989, The Mind Has No Sex?,
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
* Scott, Joan, 1991, “The Evidence of Experience”,
Critical Inquiry, 17: 773-97.
* Shapin, Steven, 1994, A Social History of Truth:
Civility and Science in Seventeenth-Century England, Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
* Sherif, Carol, 1987, “Bias in Psychology”, in
Harding 1987a.
* Smith, Dorothy, 1974, “Women's Perspective as a
Radical Critique of Sociology”, Sociological Inquiry, 44: 7-13.
* Solomon, Miriam, 2001, Social Empiricism,
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
* Spanier, Bonnie, 1995, Im/partial Science: Gender
Ideology in Molecular Biology , Bloomington, Ind.: Indiana University
Press.
* Spelman, Elizabeth, 1988, Inessential Woman,
Boston: Beacon Press.
* Stanley, Liz and Sue Wise, 1983, Breaking Out:
Feminist Consciousness and Feminist Research, London: Routledge and
Kegan Paul.
* Tavris, Carol, 1992, The Mismeasure of Women, New
York: Simon and Schuster.
* Taylor, Charles, 1985, “Neutrality in Political
Science” in Philosophy and the Human Sciences, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
* Tiles, Mary, 1987, “A Science of Mars or of
Venus?”, Philosophy, 62: 293-306.
* Tiles, Mary and Hans Oberdiek, 1995, Living in a
Technological Culture, London and New York: Routledge.
* Tuana, Nancy, (ed.), 1989, Feminism & Science,
Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
* Waring, Marilyn, 1990, If Women Counted, San
Francisco: Harper Collins.
* West, Candace and Don Zimmerman, 1987, “Doing
Gender”, Gender and Society, 1: 125-51.
* Williams, Bernard, 1978, Descartes: the Project of
Pure Enquiry, Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press.
* Wylie, Alison, 1996, “The Constitution of
Archaeological Evidence: Gender Politics and Science”, in The Disunity
of Science, P. Galison and D. Stump, (eds.), Stanford: Stanford
University Press.
* –––, 2003, “Why Standpoint Matters”, in Science
and Other Cultures, R. Figueroa and S. Harding, (eds.), New York:
Routledge.
* Young, I. M. 1990, Throwing Like a Girl and Other
Essays in Feminist Political Theory, Bloomington: Indiana University
Press.
Other Internet Resources
* Anderson, Elizabeth, 2004, “How Not to Criticize
Feminist Epistemology: a Review of Pinnick, Koertge and Almeder,
Scrutinizing Feminist Epistemology”.
* “Whose Knowledge Is it Anyway? Feminist
Epistemology and Science: An Annotated Bibliography” (by Lauren
Pressley)
* Frequently Asked Questions about Feminist Science
Studies (Association of American Colleges and Universities, 1999)
* Kelley Hays-Gilpin Webpage (resource on gender and
archaeology)
* Doing Feminist Research—Annotated Bibliography (by
Ann Hall)
* Symposia on Gender, Race, and Philosophy (Robert
Gooding-Williams, Sally Haslanger, Ishani Maitra, Ronald Sundstrom,
eds.)
* Theory of Science (includes links to articles,
bibliographies on gender & science, postmodernism, etc.)
Related Entries
epistemology: social | feminist (interventions): ethics | feminist
(interventions): social epistemology | postmodernism | scientific
knowledge: social dimensions of | testimony: epistemological problems
of