ephemera
© ephemera 2009 ISSN 1473-2866 www.ephemeraweb.org theory & politics
in organization volume 9(1): 44-51
interviews
Philosophy in the Boudoir
and the Streets: An Interview with Simon Critchley
Simon Critchley and Carl
Cederström
When I recently asked Simon Critchley in a TV-show how he ended up as a
philosopher he laconically proclaimed: ‘failure’. He claimed to have
failed not only as a musician and a poet, but also as a political
activist.
If failure was the way into philosophy for Simon Critchley, then
philosophy seems to have been the way into success. His many books have
attracted much attention and, as all philosophical works worth their
name, stirred quite some controversy: from deep resentment in some
corners, to pulsating admiration in others. Either way, he has covered
a wide range of themes, including humour, ethics, poetry, film,
literature, deconstruction and death. He has led a rather wandering
life, having lived in a number of non-exotic western-European
countries. For a few years now, however, Simon Critchley is comfortably
settled into New York, recently married, and is the holder of a chair
in philosophy at the New School for Social Research.
I met Simon Critchley at a club in Soho last summer. He had arranged a
very elegant room for the interview. It was splendid. With silk
cushions spread over the floor, and lit candelabras lined up along the
walls, it reminded me of a boudoir, perfectly suitable for
half-concealed indecencies. However, half-way through the interview, a
man and a woman, both rather tipsy, entered the room. They threw
themselves on the divan, quite arrogantly, and asked if we were doing
some drugs (I suppose two grown-up men sitting with crossed-legs on the
floor in a boudoir might evoke such an idea). Politely, yet
irritatingly, we ignored them; then, when we realized they wouldn't
leave us alone, we left, like two passive-aggressive cowards with
dismantled self-esteem, and went out on the street. We finished the
interview?– which appropriately touched on issues of courage and
comedy?– in one of those desolate Indian restaurants with blinking
fluorescent lamps. Of course, none of us mentioned the fact that we had
acted as humorless cowards back at the club. Why would we? Instead we
spoke of humour, politics and philosophy, Simon's recent controversy
with Slavoj Zizek, and whether a corporation can be ethical. It was,
all in all, a splendid night!
__________
1 The philosophy show, which was broadcasted in Sweden early 2008, can
be watched at:
http://viastream.player.mtgnewmedia.se/inner.php?TvSkin=tv8_se&PKCatID=1950
__________
Carl Cederström: You have
said that philosophy begins in disappointment, not wonder. But a common
way into philosophy seems to go through reading, say, Albert Camus,
Hermann Hesse, Jean-Paul Sartre or Bertrand Russell?– authors who often
generate a sense of youthful wonder; or, better, trigger a sense of
wondrous alienation, where the reader can identify with the image of
the rebel or the outsider, images which seem particularly appealing to
confused adolescents.
Simon Critchley: Well, for me
philosophy begins in disappointment. But youth and disappointment, I
think, are not incompatible. You could actually say that philosophy is
an experience of youth: both biographically, as a time in one's life,
and philosophically, that there is something exhilarating in the
discovery of the new. For me it was the experience of something being
stripped away, that things?– like morality, religion, politics,
ideology, and the rest?– are not the way you've been told they are. It
is an experience, an exhilarating experience, of disillusionment. So
philosophy is this excitement, not with an experience of wonder with
regard to what is, but an excitement and exhilaration with regard to
what isn't. Disappointment and excitement are, in this sense, two sides
of the same coin. There's something enormously exciting about being
disappointed, something enormously exhilarating about being
disillusioned. And that is also, as you say in your question, an
experience of rebellion.
CC: Let us swiftly turn to
politics, an important theme in your work. You have said that a
characteristic response to today's politics is a passive withdrawal
from the world. How would you like to define, or diagnose, the present
political situation?
SC: I have at least three
political categories for thinking of the present situation: military
neo-liberalism, neo-Leninism and neo-anarchism. Among these three I
think that military neo-liberalism is what best characterizes the state
of the western world. At the heart of this category is the idea of a
unification of neo-liberal economics with a certain universalization of
democracy and human rights talk, which is backed up with military
force. So the situation we're in is one where other regimes have to
accept the logic of capitalism, accept the ideology of democracy and
human rights?– and if they don't accept that, they're going to be
bombed. That's the logic of military neo-liberalism. So the world is in
a state of permanent war, in a state of chaos. In the face of a world
that is blowing itself to pieces, where, as Dostoevsky says, ‘blood is
being spilt in the merriest ways, as if it were champagne', it is
tempting to withdraw, make yourself into an island, close your eyes and
pretend as if nothing bad goes on. This response, which is both
plausible and coherent, but which I like to refuse, is what I call
passive nihilism.
CC: But the opposite response,
to actively engage in politics: dutifully go to the voting booth and to
publicly express your opinions, couldn't that also be a way of
distancing yourself? At least this is what Zizek claims in his book On
Violence, ‘that sometimes, doing nothing is the most violent thing you
could do'.
SC: I'm simply not in agreement
with Zizek here. His argument is that in a world defined by systemic
violence?– actual violence, as well as symbolic violence?– one needs to
step back, reflect and wait. For me, this is the obsessional neurotic
position, and that's why I have called Zizek, in the response I wrote
for Harper's Magazine, ‘The Slovenian Hamlet'. Hamlet lives in a world
defined by violence, where the time is out of joint, where one's father
is killed illegitimately, and where the
order of kings and social hierarchies has broken down, and as a result
Hamlet cannot act. He dreams of an act of vengeance, of which he lacks
the courage, and ends up doing nothing. In Zizek you also find this
horror of the immediacy of action. He will say things like: I have a
hat but I don't have a rabbit. I think that's overly pessimistic
although I can understand the diagnosis. What interests me are forms of
resistance, which takes into account the situation we're in, but
doesn't stop there, but goes on and tries to act in new imaginative
ways. This is where neo-anarchism comes in: as the articulation of the
possibility of new forms of coalitions, new chains of equivalence; and
in that regard, unlike Zizek, I'm not dismissive of anti-capitalist
movements of resistance and protest.
CC: This leads us to what
seems to be Zizek's main critique against your work: that the forms of
resistance you advocate, forms of resistance that retain a distance to
the state, are futile.
SC: Yes. The argument that
Zizek makes against me is that these demands are powerless?– that they
don't change anything. He's right and he's wrong. In a way, all forms
of resistance are powerless. You could even say that the history of
political resistance is one long history of failure. The student
protest in Paris, 1968, was a failure: the events took place in May,
and already on June 23 1968, De Gaulle was elected back into power. And
the list of failures goes on. What we should remember is that the
effects of resistance are often experienced retrospectively. I think
that to judge political resistance by the standards of its
effectiveness, at the level of political power by occupying the terrain
of the state, is a delusion?– a Leninist delusion. The argument here is
really an argument of state power vs. no power. For Zizek resistance is
futile; resistance is surrender. We have to occupy the terrain of the
state?– which is also the argument that Lenin makes in The State and
Revolution. This is Lenin's critique of the anarchists: that the
anarchists are unrealistic and bourgeois; that they lack the courage
and ruthlessness to accept the cruelty of political reality. So what
has to be done, according to Lenin, is occupying the state such that it
eventually withers away. The obvious historical objection is that this
never happened. Instead, the Bolshevik revolution led to the most
grotesque elevation of the state, in the form of the Soviet Union, and
to human disasters. So it could be said that the debate between Zizek
and myself is really a debate between Lenin and anarchism, or between
Marx and Bakunin. Bakunin, in his critique in the 1870s, calls Marx a
crypto-Bismarckian. He says that secretly, what Marxists want at all
costs, is state power. I, contrary to Lenin and Zizek, argue for
politics as the hegemonic articulation of an interstitial distance from
state power, that cannot simply be judged by whether power has been
taken or not. And with regard to the other issue?– whether capitalism
is here to stay or not?– I think Zizek accepts that. I also accept it,
but in a much more melancholic spirit. Who knows, but with the current
global economic crisis, perhaps a certain model of capitalism is coming
to an end. Perhaps we are living through the beginning of the end.
CC: An important addition to
this formula is comedy, more precisely how humour opens up new ways of
resistance. How does your notion of the ‘comic subject of politics'
differ from ‘classical subjects of politics'?
SC: The classical subject of
politics is a virile, active, autarchic, sovereign subject?– a subject
that can; a subject that is able to act. For me that goes together with
a certain lack of humour, whether that is Bush or Bin Laden. They are
both active virile political subjects, in some sort of bloody contest.
What interests me about comedy as a form of resistance, is that comedy
is the performance of powerlessness. The comic subject doesn't assume
it has power, doesn't assume its virility. It performs its
powerlessness, in acts of non-violent warfare?– it is the power of the
powerless.
So classical forms of the political subject are capable of acting; they
are virile, they are potent and they are humourless. But most
importantly they are justified in what they do. What interests me is to
think of a political subjectivity that would find itself inescapably
involved in acts which cannot be justified. I've been doing some work
recently on Benjamin's critique of violence and there's a fascinating
argument in Benjamin where he says that ‘law is violence, politics is
violence, but does violence exhaust the political field?' No, there's a
guideline of non-violence which to him is expressed in the biblical
prohibition of murder: ‘thou shall not kill'. The situation in which
that prohibition arises is a situation of violence: I know I cannot
kill and yet I'm in a situation where I have to kill. The violence that
I perpetrate is necessary but not justified. To think about an idea of
politics based upon a non-justifiable sphere of violence, is
fascinating. This is similar to Judith Butler's claim about mourning.
The classical political subject doesn't want to mourn, but to act.
After 9/11, there were 11 days of mourning. Then mourning was declared
to be over and it was time for action. The question that Judith Butler
asks, which I find enormously interesting, is how a politics of grief
and mourning would look like?– a politics based around the
powerlessness of grief and mourning. For me that's similar to the
structure of the superego II and the comic subject.
CC: At the same time it has
become increasingly popular among politicians to either mock
themselves, or happily subject themselves to mockery. Take Stephen
Colbert's talk at the White House Correspondent's Dinner, for example,
where he scornfully delivered jokes at Bush's expense. Would this be an
example of a powerful critique directed against the Bush administration
or, on the contrary, a type of humour which is easily co-opted and
turned into something positive for the Bush campaign?
SC: I think Stephen Colbert's
mocking of Bush was a classic example of political satire, and a very
powerful satire. It was nicely painful. I thought to myself, when I saw
it, that this is a courageous act, this is a powerful thing. But sure,
it could be co-opted. Political leaders can use humour in all sorts of
ways. We should always remember that humour is radically situational
and contextual. It can always be re-described in toothless ways.
CC: Let us stay with the
relation between humour and co-optation a little longer. In the world
of business organizations there seems to be an obsession with having
fun, being happy and to be a bit on the crazy side. We see this in many
organizations, of which Google is probably the most conspicuous.
Employees, it seems, become obliged to participate in silly activities
or whatever the organization find humorous. Does this pre- empt the
possibility of powerfully using humour as a form of resistance?
SC: I actually gave a talk at
Google recently, part of their authors@google program. They wanted me
to speak of humour, so I went there and dutifully gave my views on
humour. Of course that's a classic strategy of co-optation. But I gave
an example there, which is from my book On Humour, concerning the way
in which corporations deal with humour. The example is from a hotel in
Atlanta, where I was staying. When having breakfast one morning I saw a
group of employees in one of these huge rooms, this sort of windowless
suite you'll find in American hotels. They were engaging in structured
fun: playing kick-ball, ping-pong, frisbee, whatever?– you know, these
forms of fun and humour which are being used in order to build up the
morale amongst the employees. In this way, humour becomes a form of
compulsory happiness?– it becomes a strategy that organizations use to
impose a compulsory happiness. If you don't go along with the
structured fun, you're no fun, you're a party-pooper. So in that sense
humour can be used by organizations as a form of coercion. When I was
in the Google office you got people running around on scooters. They
also got a vast recreation room with ping-pong and plastic balls, where
you could exercise and have fun with your colleagues. This means that
the line between work and play becomes increasingly difficult to draw,
which by extension means that work never ceases?– that play becomes
another form of work, structured fun becomes a way in which the
corporation regulates and organizes the behaviour of is employees. To
that extent I think humour is extremely dangerous.
To go back to the example in Atlanta: after having watched the people
engaging in structured fun, I met a number of them outside, smoking
cigarettes and talking to each other. I asked if they were really free
to refuse to take part of this or not. And they said that they were
free to refuse but they would have been seen as bad employees or party-
poopers. So they weren't really given a choice as to whether they
wanted to be involved or not. But while smoking, they started to engage
in a series of small jokes, talking about what a shit the manager who
was organizing this was, and so on and so forth. So by standing there,
smoking and telling obscene jokes, they created a non-organizational
outside space, where they could be themselves.
So humour works in two ways in organizations. On the one hand it can be
a coercive mechanism for producing false harmony amongst the workforce.
But on the other hand, the informal circulation of humour, which occurs
particularly through dirty obscene humour, can never be controlled.
When I was working in factories in the late 70s, that's the way humour
worked: really disgusting jokes, such as photocopied sheets of paper
with vast sexual organs penetrating the secretary of the boss or the
boss himself. So humour is about regulation but can still, informally,
have a subversive potential. What we have seen though, in the last
20-30 years, is the use of humour consultants which study organizations
in order to improve their spirit of ethos, and this I find oppressive.
CC: But could we think of
something like an Ethical corporation, where the use of, say, humour
could have a subversive effect?
SC: Can corporations be
Ethical? I'm not sure. I would say that if they can, it is with great
difficulty. Corporations, by definition, incorporate. The corporation
is a sort of vast body, which you have to be part of. From a political
perspective, the corporation is a totalitarian structure by necessity.
Moments of Ethics would occur in those moments of obscene informal
contact, when people say what they really think. But the flipside of
subversion is recuperation. This lesson comes from the Situationists.
Strategies of subversion, or what the Situationists call
‘détournement', are always recuperable. And again, subversion in
humour is radically context specific. Certain jokes, at certain times,
will subvert the situation. But that same joke can be employed by the
organization, and turned into something positive, even an appetizer.
There is this example with people complaining that Stella Artois beer
was too expensive. What they, Stella Artois, did was that they
internalised the criticism and turned it into their selling point,
reassuring in their slogan that their beer was expensive. This is a
common strategy by which a critique becomes recuperated as an
organizational appetizer slogan. I think it's always like that. The
limit of subversion, or the place at which subversion can take place,
is constantly moving. New forms of humour are powerful only for a brief
period of time, after which they can be deployed by the very forces
they were originally set out to laugh at. I think this is true of every
form of humour. What that means is not that humour is useless, but that
in any organizational framework there will be new forms of informal
subversive wit, usually centred around obscenity. Obscenity is
interesting because there might be a limit to the obscene which might
not be recuperable. The obscene is an interesting category.
CC: When we're already speaking
of obscenity, let me ask you something about your relation to Lacanian
psychoanalysis, a relation which seems to be rather ambiguous. In
Infinitely Demanding you criticize Lacan and Lacanians for having
distorted the picture of human finitude by making the subject too
heroic, too authentic.
SC: Yes, my relation to Lacan
is ambiguous. In Infinitely Demanding and Ethics, Politics and
Subjectivity I claim that Lacan is heir to a tragic heroic paradigm
that begins with German idealism. My main disagreement with Lacan, and
the tragic paradigm as a whole, concerns a supposed link between
heroism and authenticity. This comes particularly out of my critique of
Heidegger. What Heidegger is up to in Being and Time?– at least this is
my understanding?– is that you must choose your hero: either you choose
das Man, the inauthentic life, or you choose yourself?– the point being
that you have to choose yourself as your hero in order to be authentic.
So my main critique of Lacan boils down to a critique of linking
authenticity with heroism, and I believe that argument has some
plausibility. Badiou, however, has made an interesting response to this
argument. He says that we could speak of a heroism of the void: a
heroism which is not a heroism of authenticity, but a heroism of the
divided subject. This means that heroism, rather than being the
completion of the subject in authenticity, becomes the name of the
evisceration of the subject in the face of an uncontrollable Event.
CC: But this is a reading which
mainly concerns Seminar VII, and not so much the later Lacan, where the
heroic subject is no longer based on an idea of pure desire?
SC: There are of course other
aspects of Lacan?– there are other Lacans, as it were?– and in this
regard I am happy to accept that my critique has its limitations. When
I'm being defensive, I say that I'm just talking about Seminar VII?–
which is also what Zizek calls the heroic moment in Lacan's teaching,
appearing in the late 1950s. In Lacan's later work it is clear that
something else happens. In Ethics Politics and Subjectivity, I say that
there is this tragic heroic moment, but that there is also a moment of
comedy. Lacan's genius in that seminar is to focus on the mute figure
of Harpo Marx, as an image of the dusting of the Thing. The play of
jokes and the comedy of the Marx Brothers, I would say, is also an
articulation of the relation to the ethical subject and the real.
I'm thinking now of doing some work on psychosis. The idea is that
there seems to be a relation between psychosis and mysticism. The
mystic tries to empty itself, annihilate itself, in order to be filled
with divine love. So the mystic achieves that glorification of his
subjectivity through touching the divine. The material body is
important here because it is through the wounding, or the marking, of
the body that the psychotic tries to communicate, and become unified,
with god. We find exactly the same structure in the psychosis of
Schreber, or, indeed, in the psychotic patients I've come across. The
material body becomes a body that is only completed in relation to the
divine. In a sense the psychotic cannot complete there own body image
without it.
CC: Are there any particular
philosophers who would symbolise this form of mystical psychosis?
SC: The philosopher who comes
to mind as the classic psychotic would be Spinoza. In Spinoza you have
the idea that through the use of reason one you attain an intellectual
understanding of the divine, of plenitude of nature. This is what he
calls ‘beatitude'. The structure we find in both mysticism and
psychosis?– the unification of the glorified body with the divine?– can
also be found in certain philosophical systems, driven by that same
fantasy of unifying the human with the divine. You could find that, as
already mentioned, in Spinoza. You can find that in the hermetic
tradition, with people like Giordano Bruno. You can also find that in
Simone Weil, who was emptying out her body, physically, by
self-starvation. She dies an anorexic death: starving herself to death,
at the same point reaching a communion with god, which is a form of
divinization of the self.
CC: Speaking of death, there's
a growing interest in transhumanist studies and other related fields
where increased longevity and, ultimately, immortality is conceived not
only as desirable but possible. This usually comes with the idea of
moving away from the human as we know it, to the post-human. What is
your relation to this type of ‘philosophy'?
SC: I think it is a terrible,
pernicious, delusion. I think the idea that we become mind, that the
human condition could be perfected through infinite longevity is a
recurrent delusion in the history of thought?– a pernicious delusion. I
want to flip things around and say that what should be questioned in
Western culture is the idea of longevity?– that a good life is the same
thing as a long life, a long life underwritten by medical science and
development in technology. I claim that the material condition of
possibility of being human is the body. The body withers and dies, it
lessens and changes, and that is the constant reminder of who we are.
For me, to be free is to accept the limitation of one's body, accepting
oneself as a material and mortal being. That involves accepting that
life is brief, and that life has to be embraced, affirmed and enjoyed
in its brevity. I don't understand the idea of the post human. I think
the human is a sick animal, maybe even an evolutionary mistake. But
that's where we are. So the whole idea of disappointment is an
acceptance of limitation: limitation, not as something limiting, but as
the condition of possibility for flourishing, of freedom and life.
Montaigne says that
he who has learned how to die has unlearned how to be a slave. What he
means is that he who has accepted the limit of mortality, has become
free. Therefore the idea of living for a thousand years is slavery for
me. As simple as that. It is an ideology of human enslavement. A
delusion which is bound up to an ideology of the future. For at least
the last 500 years that in the next 50 years there will be developments
such that we will enable us to live forever. This future is a tiny bit
further away than we can imagine, but not that far. I think it's
dreadful. There will certainly be a future, but any sort of faith in
the future is a superstition. I believe that the only way of facing the
future is by turning towards the past and listening to the counsel of
the dead, the hard lessons of history.
Simon Critchley is Professor of
Philosophy at the New School for Social Research, New York. E-mail:
critchls@newschool.edu
Carl Cederström is a PhD student
at the Institute of Economic Research, Lund University. E-mail:
carl.cerderstrom@ics.lu.se